Roscoe Pound's Sociological Jurisprudence

 Roscoe Pound, the most influential academic lawyer of the early twentieth century, described "the sociological movement in jurisprudence" as "a movement for pragmatism as a philosophy of law." A sociological jurisprudence, Pound declared, would adjust "principle and doctrines to the human conditions they are to govern rather than to assume first principles." The "human factor" would be "in the central place," and legal "logic" would be "relegated" "to its true position as an instrument. Pound's writings criticized legal decisions that relied on "rigorous logical deduction from predetermined conceptions in disregard of and often in the teeth of actual facts.In language harking back to Dewey, Pound asserted that law "must be judged by the result it achieves, not by the niceties of its eternal structure." Thus, he called for a "jurisprudence of ends" rather than a "jurisprudence of conceptions."
Proponents of sociological jurisprudence endorsed pragmatism's rejection of individual rights. By the beginning of World War I, Pound could declare that "in jurisprudence . . . the whole doctrine of natural rights has been definitively abandoned." "All natural law theories," he argued, were "purely personal and arbitrary" because such a theory could never truly resolve social conflicts "except when all men are agreed in their moral and economic views." Instead, he maintained that "the concern of the law" has always been "with social interests. His writings sought to demonstrate that legal systems had historically recognized the moral priority of the community. "Certain great social interests," he argued, "have determined the growth of law from the beginning." For example, in primitive societies "injuries to the body" were "not thought of at first as infringements of an individual interest," but rather "as involving infringement of an interest of a group or kindred or of a social interest in peace and good order." But, like Dewey, Pound recognized that "there is a social interest in the individual moral and social life." Thus, when "securing individual interests to this end, the law is securing a social interest." In fact, Pound declared that legal doctrine should satisfy Dewey's test of political insitutions: whether they would "free individual capacities in such a way as to make them available for the development of the general happiness or common good."
Sociological jurisprudence encouraged judicial activism and creativity in common law cases. In most circumstances, Pound argued, courts could achieve a "jurisprudence of ends" by devising legal doctrines that balanced the various social interests at stake in any case. Just as Dewey argued that "knowledge of the past is significant only as it deepens and extends our understanding of the present," so Pound claimed that "the function of legal history [was] one of illustrating how rules and principles have met concrete situations in the past and of enabling us to judge how we may deal with such situations in the present." Precedents, he maintained, should not be understood as "furnishing self-sufficient premises from which rules are to be obtained by rigid deduction." Thus, "the real genius of our common law" was its ability to "giv[e] a fresh illustration of [al principle to a concrete case, producing a workable and just re-suit." On these grounds, Justice Benjamin Cardozo, another prominent proponent of sociological jurisprudence, stated that one of his rules for deciding cases was "when the social needs demand one settlement rather than another, there are times when we must bend symmetry, ignore history and sacrifice custom in pursuit of other and larger ends."
However, progressive jurists insisted that courts assume a more restrained judicial stance when considering the constitutionality of a statute or governmental practice. Legislation, Pound argued, was increasingly the product of "long and patient study by experts, careful consideration by conferences or congresses or associations, press discussions in which public opinion is focused upon all important details, and hearings before legislative committees." Judges should respect the balancing of social interests reflected in legislative output because the elected branches of government had the greater capacity for discovering and analyzing the relevant social science data underlying conflicting social claims. Courts, Pound observed, had "no machinery for getting at the facts." They did not "have the advantage of legislative reference bureaus, of hearings before committees, of the testimony of specialists who have conducted detailed investigations, as the legislature can address." Furthermore, governance by elected officials was "the more truly democratic form of law-making." "Legislation," Pound insisted, was "the more direct and accurate expression of the general will." When the representatives of the people, after evaluating current circumstances, enacted specific social and economic programs, judges had to be "willing to assume that the legislature did its duty and to keep its hands off on that ground."
Historical knowledge of the original purposes of constitutional provisions was no substitute for judicial lack of social science expertise. Pragmatists insisted that past circumstances not dictate present policies. Judges, in their view, had no right to strike down legislation merely because some inconsistency was perceived with the intentions of the constitutional framers. The framers, Pound claimed, neither intended nor should have intended "to dictate philosophical or juristic beliefs and opinion to those who were to come after them." Instead, they should be interpreted as stating some general principles beyond the power of government to circumvent but leaving to future generations the power to interpret those principles in light of contemporary needs and circumstances. The authors of the constitution "laid down principles, not rules." The particular rules they favored were only "illustrations of these principles so long as facts and opinions remain what they were when the rules were announced. "
Pound aimed most of his fire at "the indifference, if not contempt" that many "courts and lawyers" showed to the economic regulations passed during the progressive era. In particular, he held that decisions striking down legislation as inconsistent with the freedom of contract were based on "rigorous logical deduction from predetermined conceptions in disregard of and often in the teeth of the actual facts." Cases like Lochner v. New York "exaggerate[d] private right at the expense of public right" and were based on "ignorance of the actual situations of fact." As a result, these manifestations of "judicial jealousy of the reform movement" "obstruct[ed] the way of social progress"; they provided "a fruitful cause of strikes, industrial discord, and consequent lawlessness."
Pound believed that the original constitution, based on many principles of natural law, probably protected certain individual rights. Indeed, he claimed that some progressive economic legislation "might have been an unreasonable deprivation of liberty as things were even 50 years ago." However, as noted above, he disagreed with such jurists as Cooley and Schroeder who insisted that judges were obligated to protect the individual rights the framers had previously placed in the Constitution. Pound maintained that courts had to consider the present implications of policies protecting those rights. The crucial constitutional question was whether regulations were "reasonable . . .as things stand now." Because courts only "have the experience of the past," but "not . . . the facts of the present," judges were not "competent to formulate rules for new relations which require regulation." "What court," Pound concluded, "that passes upon industrial legislation is able or pretends to investigate conditions of manufacture, to visit factories and see them in operation, and to take the testimony of employers, employees, physicians, social workers, and economists as to the needs of workmen and of the public, as a legislative committee may and often does?"
Although Pound's writings on constitutional theory were primarily intended to weaken the constitutional foundations of judicial activism on behalf of the individual's right to freedom of contract, said to be protected by the due process clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, Pound also believed that he successfully undermined claims that courts should strike clown legislation inconsistent with the individual's right to freedom of speech. Pound made this clear in a 1915 article, "Interests of Personality." That essay recognized that the framers of the Constitution had intended to protect the individual interest in speech. But Pound stated that under current circumstances that interest should have no more weight than "other individual interests of personality." In free speech cases, Pound asserted, the individual's interest in free speech "must always be balanced" with those social interests threatened by the speech in question. "The social interest in the security of social institutions," "disturb[ances] to the public peace [and] shocks [to] the moral feelings of the community" were among the social interests that frequently outweighed the individual's interest in free speech. Thus, Pound endorsed Lincoln's Civil War restrictions on the press and various cases in which courts upheld restrictions on speech rights.
Pound never suggested that the principles of sociological jurisprudence were hostile to every constitutional defense of free speech. In "Interests of Personality" he claimed that the social interest in open discussion provided a better ground for judicial activism on behalf of free speech. This "social interest in free belief and free expression of opinion" was one of the "guarantees of political efficiency and instruments of social progress." Indeed, Pound added that past cases demonstrated "an over-insistence upon the countervailing interest of the state in its personality or over-insistence upon the social interest in the security of some particular social institution."
Nevertheless, Pound did not give any examples of actual circumstances where the social interest in expression outweighed other social interests. Indeed, he never endorsed an opinion that protected free speech. Perhaps because "Interests of Personality" primarily discussed common law rules, Pound paid little attention to the problems that would arise when a legislature explicitly declared other social interests outweighed the social interest in free speech. Moreover, his other writings suggested that courts should give the legislature the same leeway to balance the social interest in free speech as he thought courts should give when balancing the interest in freedom of contract.
Prewar politics did not force Pound or other progressives to confront legislation that explicitly restricted free speech. For the first fifteen years of the twentieth century the elected branches of government were neither passing nor enforcing limitations on the scope of legitimate political dissent. Thus, before World War I, most progressives were unaware of the potential that pragmatism and sociological jurisprudence had for tolerating narrow interpretations of free-speech rights. The burning constitutional question of that period was the status of the freedom of contract. Pragmatism and sociological jurisprudence proved to be powerful rhetorical tools in the progressive fight for economic, political, and social reform. Because they "succeed[ed] in their office," progressives considered those ideas "reliable, sound, good, [and] true." Nevertheless, one important consequence of this wholesale adoption of pragmatism and sociological jurisprudence emerged: when federal and state governments began to pass legislation explicitly restricting political dissent, the dominant mode of legal argument in the United States was either actively hostile to the then "traditional" conservative libertarian defense of constitutional expression rights or, at best, silent about the nature of a sound constitutional defense of free speech.


No comments:

Post a Comment