*DISCLAIMER*
The
notes below are adapted from the Kenyatta University, UoN and Moi University Teaching module
and the students are adviced to take keen notice of the various legal
and judicial reforms that might have been ocassioned since the module
was adapted. the laws and statutes might also have changed or been
repealed and the students are to be wary and consult the various
statutes reffered to herein
TOPICAL OUTLINES
1.
Legal Positivism
2.
Natural Law
3.
Feminist Jurisprudence
4.
Marxist Jurisprudence
5.
Sociological Jurisprudence
Meaning and
introduction to Jurisprudence
The word jurisprudence derives
from the Latin term juris prudentia, which means "the study,
knowledge, or science of law." In the United States jurisprudence
commonly means the philosophy of law. Legal philosophy has many aspects, but
four of them are the most common. The first and the most
prevalent form of jurisprudence seeks to analyse, explain, classify,
and criticize entire bodies of law. Law school textbooks and legal
encyclopedias represent this type of scholarship. The second type of
jurisprudence compares and contrasts law with other fields of knowledge
such as literature, economics, religion, and the social sciences. The
third type of jurisprudence seeks to reveal the historical, moral, and
cultural basis of a particular legal concept. The fourth body of jurisprudence
focuses on finding the answer to such abstract questions as What is law?
How do judges (properly) decide cases?
Apart from different types of jurisprudence,
different schools of jurisprudence exist. Formalism,
or conceptualism, treats
law like math or science. Formalists believe that a judge identifies the
relevant legal principles, applies them to the facts of a case, and logically
deduces a rule that will govern the outcome of the dispute. In
contrast, proponents of legal realism believe that most cases before
courts present hard questions that judges must resolve by
balancing the interests of the parties and ultimately drawing an
arbitrary line on one side of the dispute. This line, realists maintain, is
drawn according to the political, economic, and psychological inclinations of
the judge. Some legal realists even believe that a judge is able to shape the
outcome of the case based on personal biases.
Apart from the realist-formalist dichotomy, there is the classic debate over
the appropriate sources of law between positivist and natural law schools of
thought. Positivists argue that
there is no connection between law and morality and that the only sources of law are rules that have
been expressly enacted by a governmental
entity or court of law. Naturalists, or proponents of natural
law, insist that the rules enacted by government
are not the only sources of law. They argue that moral philosophy; religion,
human reason and individual conscience are also integral
parts of the law.
There are no bright lines between different
schools of jurisprudence. The legal
philosophy of a particular legal scholar may consist of a combination of
strains from many schools of legal thought. Some scholars think that it is
more appropriate to think about jurisprudence as a continuum.
LEGAL POSITIVISM
RESEARCH DONE FROM: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/legal-positivism/
Legal
positivism is the thesis that the existence and content of law depends on
social facts and not on its merits. The English jurist John Austin
(1790-1859) formulated it thus: “The existence of law is one thing; its merit
and demerit another. Whether it be or be not is one enquiry; whether it be or
be not conformable to an assumed standard, is a different enquiry.” (1832, p.
157) The positivist thesis does not say that law's merits are unintelligible,
unimportant, or peripheral to the philosophy of law. It says that they do not
determine whether laws or legal systems exist. Whether a society has a
legal system depends on the presence of certain structures of governance, not
on the extent to which it satisfies ideals of justice, democracy, or the rule
of law. What laws are in force in that system depends on what social standards
its officials recognize as authoritative; for example, legislative enactments,
judicial decisions, or social customs. The fact that a policy would be just,
wise, efficient, or prudent is never sufficient reason for thinking that it is
actually the law, and the fact that it is unjust, unwise, inefficient or
imprudent is never sufficient reason for doubting it. According to positivism, law
is a matter of what has been posited (ordered, decided, practiced, tolerated,
etc.); as we might say in a more modern idiom, positivism is the view that law
is a social construction. Austin thought the thesis “simple and glaring.” While
it is probably the dominant view among analytically inclined philosophers of
law, it is also the subject of competing interpretations together with
persistent criticisms and misunderstandings.
1. Development and Influence
Legal
positivism has a long history and a broad influence. It has antecedents in
ancient political philosophy and is discussed, and the term itself introduced,
in mediaeval legal and political thought (see Finnis 1996). The modern
doctrine, however, owes little to these forbears. Its most important roots lie
in the conventionalist political philosophies of Hobbes and Hume, and its first
full elaboration is due to Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832) whose account Austin
adopted, modified, and popularized. For much of the next century an amalgam of
their views, according to which law is the command of a sovereign backed by
force, dominated legal positivism and English philosophical reflection about
law. By the mid-twentieth century, however, this account had lost its influence
among working legal philosophers. Its emphasis on legislative institutions was
replaced by a focus on law-applying institutions such as courts, and its
insistence of the role of coercive force gave way to theories emphasizing the
systematic and normative character of law. The most important architects of
this revised positivism are the Austrian jurist Hans Kelsen (1881-1973) and the
two dominating figures in the analytic philosophy of law, H.L.A. Hart (1907-92)
and Joseph Raz among whom there are clear lines of influence, but also
important contrasts. Legal positivism's importance, however, is not confined to
the philosophy of law. It can be seen throughout social theory, particularly in
the works of Marx, Weber, and Durkheim, and also (though here unwittingly)
among many lawyers, including the American “legal realists” and most
contemporary feminist scholars. Although they disagree on many other points,
these writers all acknowledge that law is essentially a matter of social fact.
Some of them are, it is true, uncomfortable with the label “legal positivism”
and therefore hope to escape it. Their discomfort is sometimes the product of
confusion. Lawyers often use “positivist” abusively, to condemn a formalistic
doctrine according to which law is always clear and, however pointless or
wrong, is to be rigorously applied by officials and obeyed by subjects. It is
doubtful that anyone ever held this view; but it is in any case false, it has
nothing to do with legal positivism, and it is expressly rejected by all
leading positivists. Among the philosophically literate another, more
intelligible, misunderstanding may interfere. Legal positivism is here
sometimes associated with the homonymic but independent doctrines of logical
positivism (the meaning of a sentence is its mode of verification) or
sociological positivism (social phenomena can be studied only through the
methods of natural science). While there are historical connections, and also
commonalities of temper, among these ideas, they are essentially different. The
view that the existence of law depends on social facts does not rest on a
particular semantic thesis, and it is compatible with a range of theories about
how one investigates social facts, including non-naturalistic accounts. To say
that the existence of law depends on facts and not on its merits is a thesis
about the relation among laws, facts, and merits, and not otherwise a
thesis about the individual relata. Hence, most traditional “natural law” moral
doctrines--including the belief in a universal, objective morality grounded in
human nature--do not contradict legal positivism. The only influential
positivist moral theories are the views that moral norms are valid
only if they have a source in divine commands or in social conventions. Such
theists and relativists apply to morality the constraints that legal
positivists think hold for law.
2. The Existence and Sources of Law
Every
human society has some form of social order, some way of marking and
encouraging approved behavior, deterring disapproved behavior, and resolving
disputes. What then is distinctive of societies with legal systems and, within
those societies, of their law? Before exploring some positivist answers, it
bears emphasizing that these are not the only questions worth asking. While an
understanding of the nature of law requires an account of what makes law
distinctive, it also requires an understanding of what it has in common
with other forms of social control. Some Marxists are positivists about the
nature of law while insisting that its distinguishing characteristics matter
less than its role in replicating and facilitating other forms of domination.
(Though other Marxists disagree: see Pashukanis). They think that the specific
nature of law casts little light on their primary concerns. But one can hardly
know that in advance; it depends on what the nature of law actually is.
According
to Bentham and Austin, law is a phenomenon of large societies with a sovereign:
a determinate person or group who have supreme and absolute de facto
power -- they are obeyed by all or most others but do not themselves similarly
obey anyone else. The laws in that society are a subset of the sovereign's commands:
general orders that apply to classes of actions and people and that are backed
up by threat of force or “sanction.” This imperatival theory is positivist, for
it identifies the existence of legal systems with patterns of command and
obedience that can be ascertained without considering whether the sovereign has
a moral right to rule or whether his commands are meritorious. It has two other
distinctive features. The theory is monistic: it represents all laws
as having a single form, imposing obligations on their subjects, though not on
the sovereign himself. The imperativalist acknowledges that ultimate
legislative power may be self-limiting, or limited externally by what public
opinion will tolerate, and also that legal systems contain provisions that are
not imperatives (for example, permissions, definitions, and so on). But they
regard these as part of the non-legal material that is necessary for, and part
of, every legal system. (Austin is a bit more liberal on this point). The
theory is also reductivist, for it maintains that the normative
language used in describing and stating the law -- talk of authority, rights,
obligations, and so on -- can all be analyzed without remainder in
non-normative terms, ultimately as concatenations of statements about power and
obedience.
Imperatival
theories are now without influence in legal philosophy (but see Ladenson and
Morison). What survives of their outlook is the idea that legal theory must
ultimately be rooted in some account of the political system, an insight that
came to be shared by all major positivists save Kelsen. Their particular
conception of a society under a sovereign commander, however, is friendless
(except among Foucauldians, who strangely take this relic as the ideal-type of
what they call “juridical” power). It is clear that in complex societies there
may be no one who has all the attributes of sovereignty, for ultimate authority
may be divided among organs and may itself be limited by law. Moreover, even
when “sovereignty” is not being used in its legal sense it is nonetheless a
normative concept. A legislator is one who has authority to make laws,
and not merely someone with great social power, and it is doubtful that “habits
of obedience” is a candidate reduction for explaining authority. Obedience is a
normative concept. To distinguish it from coincidental compliance we need
something like the idea of subjects being oriented to, or guided by, the
commands. Explicating this will carry us far from the power-based notions with
which classical positivism hoped to work. The imperativalists' account of
obligation is also subject to decisive objections (Hart, 1994, pp. 26-78; and
Hacker). Treating all laws as commands conceals important differences in their
social functions, in the ways they operate in practical reasoning, and in the
sort of justifications to which they are liable. For instance, laws conferring
the power to marry command nothing; they do not obligate people to marry, or
even to marry according to the prescribed formalities. Nor is reductivism any
more plausible here: we speak of legal obligations when there is no probability
of sanctions being applied and when there is no provision for sanctions (as in
the duty of the highest courts to apply the law). Moreover, we take the
existence of legal obligations to be a reason for imposing sanctions,
not merely a consequence of it.
Hans
Kelsen retains the imperativalists' monism but abandons their reductivism. On
his view, law is characterized by a basic form and basic norm.
The form of every law is that of a conditional order, directed at the courts,
to apply sanctions if a certain behavior (the “delict”) is performed. On this
view, law is an indirect system of guidance: it does not tell subjects what to
do; it tells officials what to do to its subjects under certain
conditions. Thus, what we ordinarily regard as the legal duty not to steal is
for Kelsen merely a logical correlate of the primary norm which stipulates a
sanction for stealing (1945, p. 61). The objections to imperatival monism apply
also to this more sophisticated version: the reduction misses important facts,
such as the point of having a prohibition on theft. (The courts are not
indifferent between, on the one hand, people not stealing and, on the other,
stealing and suffering the sanctions.) But in one respect the conditional
sanction theory is in worse shape than is imperativalism, for it has no
principled way to fix on the delict as the duty-defining condition of the
sanction -- that is but one of a large number of relevant antecedent
conditions, including the legal capacity of the offender, the jurisdiction of
the judge, the constitutionality of the offense, and so forth. Which among all
these is the content of a legal duty?
Kelsen's
most important contribution lies in his attack on reductivism and his doctrine
of the “basic norm.” He maintains that law is normative and must understood as
such. Might does not make right -- not even legal right -- so the philosophy of
law must explain the fact that law is taken to impose obligations on its
subjects. Moreover, law is a normative system: “Law is not, as it is
sometimes said, a rule. It is a set of rules having the kind of unity we
understand by a system” (1945, p. 3). For the imperativalists, the unity of a
legal system consists in the fact that all its laws are commanded by one
sovereign. For Kelsen, it consists in the fact that they are all links in one
chain of authority. For example, a by-law is legally valid because it is
created by a corporation lawfully exercising the powers conferred on it by the
legislature, which confers those powers in a manner provided by the
constitution, which was itself created in a way provided by an earlier
constitution. But what about the very first constitution, historically
speaking? Its authority, says Kelsen, is “presupposed.” The condition for
interpreting any legal norm as binding is that the first constitution is
validated by the following “basic norm:” “the original constitution is to
be obeyed.” Now, the basic norm cannot be a legal norm -- we cannot fully
explain the bindingness of law by reference to more law. Nor can it be a social
fact, for Kelsen maintains that the reason for the validity of a norm must
always be another norm -- no ought from is. It follows, then, that a legal
system must consist of norms all the way down. It bottoms in a hypothetical,
transcendental norm that is the condition of the intelligibility of any (and
all) other norms as binding. To “presuppose” this basic norm is not to endorse
it as good or just -- resupposition is a cognitive stance only -- but it is,
Kelsen thinks, the necessary precondition for a non-reductivist account of law
as a normative system.
There
are many difficulties with this, not least of which is the fact that if we are
willing to tolerate the basic norm as a solution it is not clear why we thought
there was a problem in the first place. One cannot say both that the basic norm
is the norm presupposing which validates all inferior norms and also that an
inferior norm is part of the legal system only if it is connected by a chain of
validity to the basic norm. We need a way into the circle. Moreover, it draws
the boundaries of legal systems incorrectly. The Canadian Constitution of 1982
was lawfully created by an Act of the U.K. Parliament, and on that basis
Canadian law and English law should be parts of a single legal system, rooted
in one basic norm: ‘The (first) U.K. constitution is to be obeyed.’ Yet no
English law is binding in Canada, and a purported repeal of the Constitution
Act by the U.K. would be without legal effect in Canada.
If law
cannot ultimately be grounded in force, or in law, or in a presupposed norm, on
what does its authority rest? The most influential solution is now H.L.A.
Hart's. His solution resembles Kelsen's in its emphasis on the normative
foundations of legal systems, but Hart rejects Kelsen's transcendentalist,
Kantian view of authority in favour of an empirical, Weberian one. For Hart,
the authority of law is social. The ultimate criterion of validity in a legal
system is neither a legal norm nor a presupposed norm, but a social rule that
exists only because it is actually practiced. Law ultimately rests on
custom: customs about who shall have the authority to decide disputes, what
they shall treat as binding reasons for decision, i.e. as sources of law, and
how customs may be changed. Of these three “secondary rules,” as Hart calls
them, the source-determining rule of recognition is most important,
for it specifies the ultimate criteria of validity in the legal system. It
exists only because it is practiced by officials, and it is not only the
recognition rule (or rules) that best explains their practice, it is rule to
which they actually appeal in arguments about what standards they are bound to
apply. Hart's account is therefore conventionalist (see Marmor, and Coleman,
2001): ultimate legal rules are social norms, although they are neither the
product of express agreement nor even conventions in the Schelling-Lewis sense
(see Green 1999). Thus for Hart too the legal system is norms all the way down,
but at its root is a social norm that has the kind of normative force that
customs have. It is a regularity of behavior towards which officials take “the
internal point of view:” they use it as a standard for guiding and evaluating
their own and others' behavior, and this use is displayed in their conduct and
speech, including the resort to various forms of social pressure to support the
rule and the ready application of normative terms such as “duty” and
“obligation” when invoking it.
It is
an important feature of Hart's account that the rule of recognition is an official
custom, and not a standard necessarily shared by the broader community. If the
imperativalists' picture of the political system was pyramidal power, Hart's is
more like Weber's rational bureaucracy. Law is normally a technical enterprise,
characterized by a division of labour. Ordinary subjects' contribution to the
existence of law may therefore amount to no more than passive compliance. Thus,
Hart's necessary and sufficient conditions for the existence of a legal system
are that “those rules of behavior which are valid according to the system's ultimate
criteria of validity must be generally obeyed, and ... its rules of recognition
specifying the criteria of legal validity and its rules of change and
adjudication must be effectively accepted as common public standards of
official behavior by its officials” (1994, p. 116). And this division of labour
is not a normatively neutral fact about law; it is politically charged, for it
sets up the possibility of law becoming remote from the life of a society, a
hazard to which Hart is acutely alert (1994, p. 117; cf. Waldron).
Although
Hart introduces the rule of recognition through a speculative anthropology of
how it might emerge in response to certain deficiencies in a customary social
order, he is not committed to the view that law is a cultural achievement. To
the contrary, the idea that legal order is always a good thing, and that
societies without it are deficient, is a familiar element of many anti-positivist
views, beginning with Henry Maine's criticism of Austin on the ground that his
theory would not apply to certain Indian villages. The objection embraces the
error it seeks to avoid. It imperialistically assumes that it is always a bad
thing to lack law, and then makes a dazzling inference from ought to is: if it
is good to have law, then each society must have it, and the concept of law
must be adjusted to show that it does. If one thinks that law is a many
splendored thing, one will be tempted by a very wide concept of law, for it
would seem improper to charge others with missing out. Positivism simply
releases the harness. Law is a distinctive form of political order, not a moral
achievement, and whether it is necessary or even useful depends entirely on its
content and context. Societies without law may be perfectly adapted to their
environments, missing nothing.
A
positivist account of the existence and content of law, along any of the above
lines, offers a theory of the validity of law in one of the two main
senses of that term (see Harris, pp. 107-111). Kelsen says that validity is the
specific mode of existence of a norm. An invalid marriage is not a special kind
of marriage having the property of invalidity; it is not a marriage at all. In
this sense a valid law one that is systemically valid in the
jurisdiction -- it is part of the legal system. This is the question that
positivists answer by reference to social sources. It is distinct from the idea
of validity as moral propriety, i.e. a sound justification for respecting the
norm. For the positivist, this depends on its merits. One indication that these
senses differ is that one may know that a society has a legal system, and know
what its laws are, without having any idea whether they are morally justified.
For example, one may know that the law of ancient Athens included the
punishment of ostracism without knowing whether it was justified, because one
does not know enough about its effects, about the social context, and so forth.
No
legal positivist argues that the systemic validity of law establishes
its moral validity, i.e. that it should be obeyed by subjects or
applied by judges. Even Hobbes, to whom this view is sometimes ascribed,
required that law actually be able to keep the peace, failing which we owe it
nothing. Bentham and Austin, as utilitarians, hold that such questions always
turn on the consequences and both acknowledge that disobedience is therefore
sometimes fully justified. Kelsen insists that “The science of law does not
prescribe that one ought to obey the commands of the creator of the
constitution” (1967, p. 204). Hart thinks that there is only a prima facie
duty to obey, grounded in and thus limited by fairness -- so there is no
obligation to unfair or pointless laws (Hart 1955). Raz goes further still,
arguing that there isn't even a prima facie duty to obey the law, not
even in a just state (Raz 1979, pp. 233-49). The peculiar accusation that
positivists believe the law is always to be obeyed is without foundation.
Hart's own view is that an overweening deference to law consorts more easily
with theories that imbue it with moral ideals, permitting “an enormous
overvaluation of the importance of the bare fact that a rule may be said to be
a valid rule of law, as if this, once declared, was conclusive of the final
moral question: ‘Ought this law to be obeyed?” (Hart 1958, p. 75).
3. Moral Principles and the Boundaries of Law
The
most influential criticisms of legal positivism all flow, in one way or
another, from the suspicion that it fails to give morality its due. A theory
that insists on the facticity of law seems to contribute little to our
understanding that law has important functions in making human life go well,
that the rule of law is a prized ideal, and that the language and practice of
law is highly moralized. Accordingly, positivism's critics maintain that the
most important features of law are not to be found in its source-based
character, but in law's capacity to advance the common good, to secure human
rights, or to govern with integrity. (It is a curious fact about
anti-positivist theories that, while they all insist on the moral nature of
law, without exception they take its moral nature to be something good.
The idea that law might of its very nature be morally problematic does not seem
to have occurred to them.)
It is
beyond doubt that moral and political considerations bear on legal philosophy.
As Finnis says, the reasons we have for establishing, maintaining or reforming
law include moral reasons, and these reasons therefore shape our legal concepts
(p. 204). But which concepts? Once one concedes, as Finnis does, that
the existence and content of law can be identified without recourse to moral
argument, and that “human law is artefact and artifice; and not a conclusion
from moral premises,” (p. 205) the Thomistic apparatus he tries to resuscitate
is largely irrelevant to the truth of legal positivism. This vitiates also Lon
Fuller's criticisms of Hart (Fuller, 1958 and 1969). Apart from some confused
claims about adjudication, Fuller has two main points. First, he thinks that it
isn't enough for a legal system to rest on customary social rules, since law
could not guide behavior without also being at least minimally clear,
consistent, public, prospective and so on -- that is, without exhibiting to
some degree those virtues collectively called “the rule of law.” It suffices to
note that this is perfectly consistent with law being source-based. Even if
moral properties were identical with, or supervened upon, these rule-of-law
properties, they do so in virtue of their rule-like character, and not their
law-like character. Whatever virtues inhere in or follow from clear,
consistent, prospective, and open practices can be found not only in law but in
all other social practices with those features, including custom and positive
morality. And these virtues are minor: there is little to be said in favour of
a clear, consistent, prospective, public and impartially administered system of
racial segregation, for example. Fuller's second worry is that if law is a
matter of fact, then we are without an explanation of the duty to obey. He
gloatingly asks how “an amoral datum called law could have the peculiar quality
of creating an obligation to obey it” (Fuller, 1958). One possibility he
neglects is that it doesn't. The fact that law claims to obligate is,
of course, a different matter and is susceptible to other explanations (Green
2001). But even if Fuller is right in his unargued assumption, the “peculiar
quality” whose existence he doubts is a familiar feature of many moral
practices. Compare promises: whether a society has a practice of promising, and
what someone has promised to do, are matters of social fact. Yet promising
creates moral obligations of performance or compensation. An “amoral datum” may
indeed figure, together with other premises, in a sound argument to moral conclusions.
While
Finnis and Fuller's views are thus compatible with the positivist thesis, the
same cannot be said of Ronald Dworkin's important works (Dworkin 1978 and
1986). Positivism's most significant critic rejects the theory on every
conceivable level. He denies that there can be any general theory of
the existence and content of law; he denies that local theories of particular
legal systems can identify law without recourse to its merits, and he rejects
the whole institutional focus of positivism. A theory of law is for Dworkin a
theory of how cases ought to be decided and it begins, not with an account of
political organization, but with an abstract ideal regulating the conditions
under which governments may use coercive force over their subjects. Force must
only be deployed, he claims, in accordance with principles laid down in
advance. A society has a legal system only when, and to the extent that,
it honors this ideal, and its law is the set of all considerations that the
courts of such a society would be morally justified in applying, whether or not
those considerations are determined by any source. To identify the law of a
given society we must engage in moral and political argument, for the law is
whatever requirements are consistent with an interpretation of its legal
practices (subject to a threshold condition of fit) that shows them to be best
justified in light of the animating ideal. In addition to those philosophical
considerations, Dworkin invokes two features of the phenomenology of judging,
as he sees it. He finds deep controversy among lawyers and judges
about how important cases should be decided, and he finds diversity in
the considerations that they hold relevant to deciding them. The controversy
suggests to him that law cannot rest on an official consensus, and the
diversity suggests that there is no single social rule that validates all
relevant reasons, moral and non-moral, for judicial decisions.
Dworkin's
rich and complex arguments have attracted various lines of reply from positivists.
One response denies the relevance of the phenomenological claims. Controversy
is a matter of degree, and a consensus-defeating amount of it is not proved by
the existence of adversarial argument in the high courts, or indeed in any
courts. As important is the broad range of settled law that gives rise to few
doubts and which guides social life outside the courtroom. As for the
diversity argument, so far from being a refutation of positivism, this is an
entailment of it. Positivism identifies law, not with all valid reasons for
decision, but only with the source-based subset of them. It is no part of the
positivist claim that the rule of recognition tells us how to decide cases, or
even tells us all the relevant reasons for decision. Positivists accept that
moral, political or economic considerations are properly operative in some
legal decisions, just as linguistic or logical ones are. Modus ponens
holds in court as much as outside, but not because it was enacted by the
legislature or decided by the judges, and the fact that there is no social rule
that validates both modus ponens and also the Municipalities Act is
true but irrelevant. The authority of principles of logic (or morality) is not
something to be explained by legal philosophy; the authority of acts of
Parliament must be; and accounting for the difference is a central task of the
philosophy of law.
Other
positivists respond differently to Dworkin's phenomenological points, accepting
their relevance but modifying the theory to accommodate them. So-called
“inclusive positivists” (e.g., Waluchow (to whom the term is due), Coleman,
Soper and Lyons) argue that the merit-based considerations may indeed be part
of the law, if they are explicitly or implicitly made so by source-based
considerations. For example, Canada's constitution explicitly authorizes for
breach of Charter rights, “such remedy as the court considers appropriate and
just in the circumstances.” In determining which remedies might be legally
valid, judges are thus expressly told to take into account their morality. And
judges may develop a settled practice of doing this whether or not it is
required by any enactment; it may become customary practice in certain types of
cases. Reference to moral principles may also be implicit in the web of
judge-made law, for instance in the common law principle that no one should
profit from his own wrongdoing. Such moral considerations, inclusivists claim,
are part of the law because the sources make it so, and thus Dworkin
is right that the existence and content of law turns on its merits, and wrong
only in his explanation of this fact. Legal validity depends on morality, not
because of the interpretative consequences of some ideal about how the
government may use force, but because that is one of the things that may be
customarily recognized as an ultimate determinant of legal validity. It is the
sources that make the merits relevant.
To
understand and assess this response, some preliminary clarifications are
needed. First, it is not plausible to hold that the merits are relevant to a
judicial decision only when the sources make it so. It would be odd to
think that justice is a reason for decision only because some source
directs an official to decide justly. It is of the nature of justice that it
properly bears on certain controversies. In legal decisions, especially
important ones, moral and political considerations are present of their own
authority; they do not need sources to propel them into action. On the
contrary, we expect to see a sourceÑa statute, a decision, or a conventionÑwhen
judges are constrained not to appeal directly to the merits. Second,
the fact that there is moral language in judicial decisions does not establish
the presence of moral tests for law, for sources come in various guises. What
sounds like moral reasoning in the courts is sometimes really source-based
reasoning. For example, when the Supreme Court of Canada says that a
publication is criminally “obscene” only if it is harmful, it is not applying
J.S. Mill's harm principle, for what that court means by “harmful” is that it
is regarded by the community as degrading or intolerable. Those are
source-based matters, not moral ones. This is just one of many appeals to positive
morality, i.e. to the moral customs actually practiced by a given society, and
no one denies that positive morality may be a source of law. Moreover, it is
important to remember that law is dynamic and that even a decision that does
apply morality itself becomes a source of law, in the first instance
for the parties and possibly for others as well. Over time, by the doctrine of
precedent where it exists or through the gradual emergence of an interpretative
convention where it does not, this gives a factual edge to normative terms.
Thus, if a court decides that money damages are in some instances not
a “just remedy” then this fact will join with others in fixing what “justice”
means for these purposes. This process may ultimately detach legal concepts
from their moral analogs (thus, legal “murder” may require no intention to
kill, legal “fault” no moral blameworthiness, an “equitable” remedy may be
manifestly unfair, etc.)
Bearing
in mind these complications, however, there undeniably remains a great deal of
moral reasoning in adjudication. Courts are often called on to decide what
would reasonable, fair, just, cruel, etc. by explicit or implicit requirement
of statute or common law, or because this is the only proper or intelligible
way to decide. Hart sees this as happening pre-eminently in hard cases in which,
owing to the indeterminacy of legal rules or conflicts among them, judges are
left with the discretion to make new law. “Discretion,” however, may
be a potentially misleading term here. First, discretionary judgments are not
arbitrary: they are guided by merit-based considerations, and they may also be
guided by law even though not fully determined by it -- judges may be empowered
to make certain decisions and yet under a legal duty to make them in a
particular way, say, in conformity with the spirit of preexisting law or with
certain moral principles (Raz 1994, pp. 238-53). Second, Hart's account might
wrongly be taken to suggest that there are fundamentally two kinds of cases,
easy ones and hard ones, distinguished by the sorts of reasoning appropriate to
each. A more perspicuous way of putting it would be to say that there are two
kinds of reasons that are operative in every case: source-based
reasons and non-source-based reasons. Law application and law creation are
continuous activities for, as Kelsen correctly argued, every legal
decision is partly determined by law and partly underdetermined: “The higher
norm cannot bind in every direction the act by which it is applied. There must
always be more or less room for discretion, so that the higher norm in relation
to the lower one can only have the character of a frame to be filled by this
act” (1967, p. 349). This is a general truth about norms. There are infinitely
many ways of complying with a command to “close the door” (quickly or slowly,
with one's right hand or left, etc.) Thus, even an “easy case” will contain
discretionary elements. Sometimes such residual discretion is of little
importance; sometimes it is central; and a shift from marginal to major can
happen in a flash with changes in social or technological circumstances. That
is one of the reasons for rejecting a strict doctrine of separation of powers
-- Austin called it a “childish fiction” -- according to which judges only
apply and never make the law, and with it any literal interpretation of
Dworkin's ideal that coercion be deployed only according to principles laid
down in advance.
It has
to be said, however, that Hart himself does not consistently view legal
references to morality as marking a zone of discretion. In a passing remark in
the first edition of The Concept of Law, he writes, “In some legal
systems, as in the United States, the ultimate criteria of legal validity
explicitly incorporate principles of justice or substantive moral values …”
(1994, p. 204). This thought sits uneasily with other doctrines of importance
to his theory. For Hart also says that when judges exercise moral judgment in
the penumbra of legal rules to suppose that their results were already part of
existing law is “in effect, an invitation to revise our concept of
what a legal rule is …” (1958, p. 72). The concept of a legal rule, that is,
does not include all correctly reasoned elaborations or determinations of that
rule. Later, however, Hart comes to see his remark about the U.S. constitution
as foreshadowing inclusive positivism (“soft positivism,” as he calls it).
Hart's reasons for this shift are obscure (Green 1996). He remained clear about
how we should understand ordinary statutory interpretation, for instance, where
the legislature has directed that an applicant should have a “reasonable time”
or that a regulator may permit only a “fair price:” these grant a bounded
discretion to decide the cases on their merits. Why then does Hart -- and even
more insistently, Waluchow and Coleman -- come to regard constitutional
adjudication differently? Is there any reason to think that a constitution
permitting only a “just remedy” requires a different analysis than a statute
permitting only a “fair rate?”
One
might hazard the following guess. Some of these philosophers think that
constitutional law expresses the ultimate criteria of legal validity: because
unjust remedies are constitutionally invalid and void ab initio,
legally speaking they never existed (Waluchow). That being so, morality
sometimes determines the existence or content of law. If this is the underlying
intuition, it is misleading, for the rule of recognition is not to be found in
constitutions. The rule of recognition is the ultimate criterion (or
set of criteria) of legal validity. If one knows what the constitution of a
country is, one knows some of its law; but one may know what the rule of
recognition is without knowing any of its laws. You may know that acts
of the Bundestag are a source of law in Germany but not be able to name or
interpret a single one of them. And constitutional law is itself subject
to the ultimate criteria of systemic validity. Whether a statute, decision or
convention is part of a country's constitution can only be determined by
applying the rule of recognition. The provisions of the 14th
Amendment to the U.S. constitution, for example, are not the rule of
recognition in the U.S., for there is an intra-systemic answer to the question
why that Amendment is valid law. The U.S. constitution, like that of all other
countries, is law only because it was created in ways provided by law (through
amendment or court decision) or in ways that came to be accepted as creating
law (by constitutional convention and custom). Constitutional cases thus raise
no philosophical issue not already present in ordinary statutory
interpretation, where inclusive positivists seem content with the theory of
judicial discretion. It is, of course, open to them to adopt a unified view and
treat every explicit or implicit legal reference to morality -- in
cases, statutes, constitutions, and customs -- as establishing moral tests for
the existence of law. (Although at that point it is unclear how their view
would differ from Dworkin's.) So we should consider the wider question: why not
regard as law everything referred to by law?
Exclusive
positivists offer three main arguments for stopping at social sources. The
first and most important is that it captures and systematizes distinctions we
regularly make and that we have good reason to continue to make. We assign
blame and responsibility differently when we think that a bad decision was
mandated by the sources than we do when we think that it flowed from a judge's
exercise of moral or political judgement. When considering who should be
appointed to the judiciary, we are concerned not only with their acumen as
jurists, but also with their morality and politics--and we take different
things as evidence of these traits. These are deeply entrenched distinctions,
and there is no reason to abandon them.
The
second reason for stopping at sources is that this is demonstrably consistent
with key features of law's role in practical reasoning. The most important
argument to this conclusion is due to Raz (1994, pp. 210-37). For a related
argument see Shapiro. For criticism see Perry, Waluchow, Coleman 2001, and
Himma.) Although law does not necessarily have legitimate authority, it lays
claim to it, and can intelligibly do so only if it is the kind of thing that could
have legitimate authority. It may fail, therefore, in certain ways only, for
example, by being unjust, pointless, or ineffective. But law cannot fail to be
a candidate authority, for it is constituted in that role by our
political practices. According to Raz, practical authorities mediate between
subjects and the ultimate reasons for which they should act. Authorities'
directives should be based on such reasons, and they are justified only when
compliance with the directives makes it more likely that people will comply
with the underlying reasons that apply to them. But they can do that
only if is possible to know what the directives require independent of appeal
to those underlying reasons. Consider an example. Suppose we agree to resolve a
dispute by consensus, but that after much discussion find ourselves in disagreement
about whether some point is in fact part of the consensus view. It will do
nothing to say that we should adopt it if it is indeed properly part of the
consensus. On the other hand, we could agree to adopt it if it were endorsed by
a majority vote, for we could determine the outcome of a vote without appeal to
our ideas about what the consensus should be. Social sources can play this
mediating role between persons and ultimate reasons, and because the nature of
law is partly determined by its role in giving practical guidance, there is a
theoretical reason for stopping at source-based considerations.
The
third argument challenges an underlying idea of inclusive positivism, what we
might call the Midas Principle. “Just as everything King Midas touched turned
into gold, everything to which law refers becomes law … ” (Kelsen 1967, p.
161). Kelsen thought that it followed from this principle that “It is …
possible for the legal order, by obliging the law-creating organs to respect or
apply certain moral norms or political principles or opinions of experts to
transform these norms, principles, or opinions into legal norms, and thus into
sources of law” (Kelsen 1945, p. 132). (Though he regarded this transformation
as effected by a sort of tacit legislation.) If sound, the Midas Principle
holds in general and not only with respect to morality, as Kelsen makes clear.
Suppose then that the Income Tax Act penalizes overdue accounts at 8% per
annum. In a relevant case, an official can determine the content of a legal
obligation only by calculating compound interest. Does this make mathematics
part of the law? A contrary indication is that it is not subject to the rules
of change in a legal system -- neither courts nor legislators can repeal or
amend the law of commutativity. The same holds of other social norms, including
the norms of foreign legal systems. A conflict-of-laws rule may direct a
Canadian judge to apply Mexican law in a Canadian case. The conflicts rule
is obviously part of the Canadian legal system. But the rule of Mexican law is
not, for although Canadian officials can decide whether or not to apply it,
they can neither change it nor repeal it, and best explanation for its
existence and content makes no reference to Canadian society or its political system.
In like manner, moral standards, logic, mathematics, principles of statistical
inference, or English grammar, though all properly applied in cases, are not
themselves the law, for legal organs have applicative but not creative power
over them. The inclusivist thesis is actually groping towards an important, but
different, truth. Law is an open normative system (Raz 1975, pp.
152-54): it adopts and enforces many other standards, including moral norms and
the rules of social groups. There is no warrant for adopting the Midas
Principle to explain how or why it does this.
4. Law and Its Merits
It may
clarify the philosophical stakes in legal positivism by comparing it to a
number of other theses with which it is sometimes wrongly identified, and not
only by its opponents. (See also Hart, 1958, Fuesser, and Schauer.)
4.1 The Fallibility Thesis
Law
does not necessarily satisfy the conditions by which it is appropriately
assessed (Lyons 1984, p. 63, Hart 1994, pp. 185-6). Law should be just, but it
may not be; it should promote the common good, but sometimes it doesn't; it
should protect moral rights, but it may fail miserably. This we may call the
moral fallibility thesis. The thesis is correct, but it is not the exclusive
property of positivism. Aquinas accepts it, Fuller accepts it, Finnis accepts
it, and Dworkin accepts it. Only a crude misunderstanding of ideas like
Aquinas's claim that “an unjust law seems to be no law at all” might suggest
the contrary. Law may have an essentially moral character and yet be morally
deficient. Even if every law always does one kind of justice (formal justice;
justice according to law), this does not entail that it does every kind of
justice. Even if every law has a prima facie claim to be applied or obeyed, it
does not follow that it has such a claim all things considered. The gap between
these partial and conclusive judgments is all a natural law theory needs to
accommodate the fallibility thesis. It is sometimes said that positivism gives
a more secure grasp on the fallibility of law, for once we see that it
is a social construction we will be less likely to accord it inappropriate
deference and better prepared to engage in a clear-headed moral appraisal of
the law. This claim has appealed to several positivists, including Bentham and
Hart. But while this might follow from the truth of positivism, it cannot
provide an argument for it. If law has an essentially moral character then it
is obfuscating, not clarifying, to describe it as a source-based structure of
governance.
4.2 The Separability Thesis
At one
point, Hart identifies legal positivism with “the simple contention that it is
no sense a necessary truth that laws reproduce or satisfy certain demands of
morality, though in fact they have often done so” (1994, pp. 185-86). Many
other philosophers, encouraged also by the title of Hart's famous essay,
“Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals,” (1958) treat the theory as
the denial that there is a necessary connection between law and morality --
they must be in some sense “separable” even if not in fact separate (Coleman,
1982). The separability thesis is generally construed so as to tolerate any contingent
connection between morality and law, provided only that it is conceivable
that the connection might fail. Thus, the separability thesis is consistent
with all of the following: (i) moral principles are part of the law; (ii) law
is usually, or even always in fact, valuable; (iii) the best explanation for
the content of a society's laws includes reference to the moral ideals current
in that society; and (iv) a legal system cannot survive unless it is seen to
be, and thus in some measure actually is, just. All four claims are counted by
the separability thesis as contingent connections only; they do not hold of all
possible legal systems -- they probably don't even hold of all
historical legal systems. As merely contingent truths, it is imagined that they
do not affect the concept of law itself. (This is a defective view of
concept-formation, but we may ignore that for these purposes.) If we think of
the positivist thesis this way, we might interpret the difference between
exclusive and inclusive positivism in terms of the scope of the modal operator:
(EP) It is necessarily the case that there is no connection between law and
morality.
(IP) It is
not necessarily the case that there is a connection between law and morality.
In
reality, however, legal positivism is not to be identified with either thesis
and each of them is false. There are many necessary “connections,” trivial and
non-trivial, between law and morality. As John Gardner notes, legal positivism
takes a position only one of them, it rejects any dependence of the
existence of law on its merits (Gardner 2001). And with respect to this
dependency relation, legal positivists are concerned with much more than the
relationship between law and morality, for in the only sense in which
they insist on a separation of law and morals they must insist also--and for
the same reasons--on a separation of law and economics.
To exclude
this dependency relation, however, is to leave intact many other interesting
possibilities. For instance, it is possible that moral value derives
from the sheer existence of law (Raz 1990, 165-70) If Hobbes is right, any
order is better than chaos and in some circumstances order may be achievable
only through positive law. Or perhaps in a Hegelian way every existing legal
system expresses deliberate governance in a world otherwise dominated by
chance; law is the spirit of the community come to self-consciousness. Notice
that these claims are consistent with the fallibility thesis, for they do not
deny that these supposedly good things might also bring evils, such as too much
order or the will to power. Perhaps such derivative connections between law and
morality are thought innocuous on the ground that they show more about human
nature than they do about the nature of law. The same cannot be said of the
following necessary connections between law and morality, each of which goes
right to the heart of our concept of law:
(1) Necessarily, law deals with moral matters.
Kelsen
writes, “Just as natural and positive law govern the same subject-matter, and
relate, therefore, to the same norm-object, namely the mutual relationships of
men -- so both also have in common the universal form of this governance,
namely obligation.” (Kelsen 1928, p. 34) This is a matter of the
content of all legal systems. Where there is law there is also morality, and
they regulate the same matters by analogous techniques. Of course to say that
law deals with morality's subject matter is not to say that it does so well,
and to say that all legal systems create obligations is not to endorse the
duties so created. This is broader than Hart's “minimum content” thesis
according to which there are basic rules governing violence, property,
fidelity, and kinship that any legal system must encompass if it aims at the
survival of social creatures like ourselves (Hart 1994, pp. 193-200). Hart
regards this as a matter of “natural necessity” and in that measure is willing
to qualify his endorsement of the separability thesis. But even a society that
prefers national glory or the worship of gods to survival will charge its legal
system with the same tasks its morality pursues, so the necessary content of
law is not dependent, as Hart thinks it is, on assuming certain facts about
human nature and certain aims of social existence. He fails to notice that if
human nature and life were different, then morality would be too and if law had
any role in that society, it would inevitably deal with morality's subject
matter. Unlike the rules of a health club, law has broad scope and reaches to
the most important things in any society, whatever they may be. Indeed, our
most urgent political worries about law and its claims flow from just this
capacity to regulate our most vital interests, and law's wide reach must figure
in any argument about its legitimacy and its claim to obedience.
(2) Necessarily, law makes moral claims on its subjects.
The
law tells us what we must do, not merely what it would be virtuous or
advantageous to do, and it requires us to act without regard to our individual
self-interest but in the interests of other individuals, or in the public
interest more generally (except when law itself permits otherwise). That is to
say, law purports to obligate us. But to make categorical demands that people
should act in the interests of others is to make moral demands on them. These
demands may be misguided or unjustified for law is fallible; they may be made
in a spirit that is cynical or half-hearted; but they must be the kind of thing
that can be offered as, and possibly taken as, obligation-imposing
requirements. For this reason neither a regime of “stark imperatives” (see
Kramer, pp. 83-9) nor a price system would be a system of law, for neither
could even lay claim to obligate its subjects. As with many other social
institutions, what law, though its officials, claims determines its character
independent of the truth or validity of those claims. Popes, for example, claim
apostolic succession from St. Peter. The fact that they claim this partly
determines what it is to be a Pope, even if it is a fiction, and even the Pope
himself doubts its truth. The nature of law is similarly shaped by the self-image
it adopts and projects to its subjects. To make moral demands on their
compliance is to stake out a certain territory, to invite certain kinds of
support and, possibly, opposition. It is precisely because law makes these
claims that doctrines of legitimacy and political obligation take the shape and
importance that they do.
(3) Necessarily, law is justice-apt.
In
view of the normative function of law in creating and enforcing obligations and
rights, it always makes sense to ask whether law is just, and where it
is found deficient to demand reform. Legal systems are therefore the kind of
thing that is apt for appraisal as just or unjust. This is a very
significant feature of law. Not all human practices are justice-apt. It makes
no sense to ask whether a certain fugue is just or to demand that it become so.
The musical standards of fugal excellence are preeminently internal -- a good
fugue is a good example of its genre; it should be melodic, interesting,
inventive etc. -- and the further we get from these internal standards the less
secure evaluative judgments about it become. While some formalists flirt with
similar ideas about law, this is in fact inconsistent with law's place amongst
human practices. Even if law has internal standards of merit -- virtues uniquely
its own that inhere in its law-like character -- these cannot preclude or
displace its assessment on independent criteria of justice. A fugue may be at
its best when it has all the virtues of fugacity; but law is not best
when it excels in legality; law must also be just. A society may therefore
suffer not only from too little of the rule of law, but also from too much of
it. This does not presuppose that justice is the only, or even the first,
virtue of a legal system. It means that our concern for its justice as one of
its virtues cannot be sidelined by any claim of the sort that law's purpose is
to be law, to its most excellent degree. Law stands continuously exposed to
demands for justification, and that too shapes its nature and role in our lives
and culture.
These
three theses establish connections between law and morality that are both
necessary and highly significant. Each of them is consistent with the
positivist thesis that the existence and content of law depends on social
facts, not on its merits. Each of them contributes to an understanding of the
nature of law. The familiar idea that legal positivism insists on the
separability of law and morality is therefore significantly mistaken.
4.3 The Neutrality Thesis
The
necessary content thesis and the justice-aptitude thesis together establish
that law is not value-neutral. Although some lawyers regard this idea
as a revelation (and others as provocation) it is in fact banal. The thought
that law could be value neutral does not even rise to falsity -- it is simply
incoherent. Law is a normative system, promoting certain values and repressing
others. Law is not neutral between victim and murderer or between owner and
thief. When people complain of the law's lack of neutrality, they are in fact voicing
very different aspirations, such as the demand that it be fair, just,
impartial, and so forth. A condition of law's achieving any of these ideals is
that it is not neutral in either its aims or its effects.
Positivism
is however sometimes more credibly associated with the idea that legal
philosophy is or should be value-neutral. Kelsen, for example, says, “the
function of the science of law is not the evaluation of its subject, but its
value-free description” (1967, p. 68) and Hart at one point described his work
as “descriptive sociology” (1994, p. v). Since it is well known that there are
convincing arguments for the ineliminability of values in the social sciences,
those who have taken on board Quinian holisms, Kuhnian paradigms, or
Foucauldian espistemes, may suppose that positivism should be rejected a
priori, as promising something that no theory can deliver.
There
are complex questions here, but some advance may be made by noticing that
Kelsen's alternatives are a false dichotomy. Legal positivism is indeed not an
“evaluation of its subject”, i.e., an evaluation of the law. And to
say that the existence of law depends on social facts does not commit one to
thinking that it is a good thing that this is so. (Nor does it preclude it: see
MacCormick and Campbell) Thus far Kelsen is on secure ground. But it does not
follow that legal philosophy therefore offers a “value-free description” of its
subject. There can be no such thing. Whatever the relation between facts and
values, there is no doubt about the relationship between descriptions
and values. Every description is value-laden. It selects and systematizes only
a subset of the infinite number of facts about its subject. To describe law as
resting on customary social rules is to omit many other truths about it
including, for example, truths about its connection to the demand for paper or
silk. Our warrant for doing this must rest on the view that the former facts
are more important than the latter. In this way, all descriptions express
choices about what is salient or significant, and these in turn cannot be
understood without reference to values. So legal philosophy, even if not
directly an evaluation of its subject is nonetheless “indirectly evaluative”
(Dickson, 2001). Moreover, “law” itself is an anthropocentric subject,
dependent not merely on our sensory embodiment but also, as its necessary
connections to morality show, on our moral sense and capacities. Legal kinds
such as courts, decisions, and rules will not appear in a purely physical
description of the universe and may not even appear in every social
description. (This may limit the prospects for a “naturalized” jurisprudence;
though for a spirited defense of the contrary view, see Leiter)
It may
seem, however, that legal positivism at least requires a stand on the so-called
“fact-value” problem. There is no doubt that certain positivists, especially
Kelsen, believe this to be so. In reality, positivism may cohabit with a range
of views here -- value statements may be entailed by factual statements; values
may supervene on facts; values may be kind of fact. Legal positivism requires
only that it be in virtue of its facticity rather than its meritoriousness that
something is law, and that we can describe that facticity without assessing its
merits. In this regard, it is important to bear in mind that not every kind of
evaluative statement would count among the merits of a given rule; its merits
are only those values that could bear on its justification.
Evaluative
argument is, of course, central to the philosophy of law more generally. No
legal philosopher can be only a legal positivist. A complete theory of
law requires also an account of what kinds of things could possibly count as
merits of law (must law be efficient or elegant as well as just?); of what role
law should play in adjudication (should valid law always be applied?); of what
claim law has on our obedience (is there a duty to obey?); and also of the
pivotal questions of what laws we should have and whether we should have law at
all. Legal positivism does not aspire to answer these questions, though its
claim that the existence and content of law depends only on social facts does
give them shape.
West Africa Review (2001)
ISSN: 1525-4488
CHOOSING A LEGAL THEORY ON CULTURAL GROUNDS: AN
AFRICAN CASE FOR LEGAL POSITIVISM
Introduction
If there are two or more legal
theories or philosophies to choose from, what sort of considerations might
induce one to prefer one to the other(s)? The standard answer to this question
is that for the choice to be a reasonable one, it must be based on an estimate
of theoretical advantage or moral benefits or both. In other words, the choice
must be based on the judgment that one of the theories is superior to the
other(s), in the way in which it would advance and clarify our theoretical
inquiries on the nature of law, or in the way in which it would advance and
clarify our moral deliberations about the law, or, in the way in which it would
do both.1
Neither of these two considerations is peculiar to the domain of legal theory.
The adoption or rejection of theories on conceptual and\or on pragmatic grounds
is an integral part of the enterprise of theory construction in all aspects of
science; moral consideration is the essence of practical reasoning; legal
theory is just an aspect of practical reasoning.
In the mainstream Anglo-Saxon legal theory, the debate
on the choice of a legal theory has revolved largely around these two broad
considerations – theoretical or moral advantage or both.2 While this
debate rages on, some African writers on legal theory have introduced a new and
potentially interesting dimension to the discourse. These writers claim to have
based their preference for one legal theory, and their opposition to another,
on what we may simply refer to as cultural grounds. Without exception, these
African commentators claim to have reached the conclusion that the positivist
legal theory is unsuitable for the African (especially the Nigerian) legal
system, and they have subsequently proceeded to advocate the adoption of the
natural law theory.3
To the extent that legal positivism claims to be a
universally valid and applicable theory, no doubt, its credibility would be
substantially diminished, if it can be shown to be either incapable of providing
an adequate description of, or of responding adequately to, the peculiar
jurisprudential experiences and needs of certain cultures, or, to be peculiarly
susceptible to morally undesirable consequences, when put into practice in
certain cultural milieu. That legal positivism is defective in both of these
ways, when applied in the African socio-political environment, is precisely
what these writers are individually out to demonstrate.
In this paper, I propose to examine the arguments
variously advanced by these African writers to support their culture-based
rejection of the positivist creed in legal theory. I will argue that creative
and interesting as these criticisms of the positivist theory may be, they are
philosophically unacceptable. As against the near universal advocacy in favour
of the natural law doctrine (legal positivism’s conceptual archrival) by the
Nigerian writers, I shall sketch the outlines of a positive case for the
adoption of legal positivism by the legal systems of modern African states.
In the remainder of this paper, I proceed as follows.
I will undertake some conceptual clarifications in section one. Here, I analyze
what is involved in the choice or adoption of a legal theory. How might a legal
system be said to have adopted a legal theory? In section two, I will explicate
the salient tenets of the positivist legal theory. What major changes have
taken place in the development of the theory, from its classic statements in
the writings of Jeremy Bentham and his disciple, John Austin, in the first half
of the nineteenth century? How have the African commentators tended to
interpret the theory? I will subject the arguments adduced by these writers for
the rejection of legal positivism to critical examination in part three. My
conclusion will be that most of these arguments are either incomplete,
irrelevant, or otherwise philosophically unsound. Finally, in the constructive
part four, I present the outlines of an argument for the adoption of the
positivist theory by our legal systems in modern day Africa.
Conceptual Clarification
There are two distinct (possibly complementary) ways
in which a legal theory could be said to have been adopted by a legal system.
In the first sense – say, with particular reference to legal positivism – a
situation could prevail in which the positivist philosophy exerts an indirect,
although possibly profound or even dominant intellectual influence on the
practices and discourse in a legal system, through the works of leading jurists
and legal scholars. In other words, influential jurists and scholars operating
in a legal system might consider legal positivism the soundest theory of law.
Such jurists and scholars may then reflect the positivist principles and
teachings in their works, either as practicing lawyers, judges, or legal
theoreticians. A situation might develop where jurists and legal scholars of
positivist persuasion constitute a significant majority or, otherwise wield
significant influence on the system’s institutions and practices. This may be
due to the strategic importance of the positions they occupy in the scheme of
things (e.g., offices that attract high visibility, like a Supreme Court
justiceship, a justice ministership, or even deans or prominent professors of
pace-setting law schools). The general orientation of the legal system in which
they operate might then become identifiably positivistic. When that happens, I
would consider legal positivism to have been indirectly adopted by the legal
system in question.4
The second sense in which a legal theory – again, say,
legal positivism – could be said to have been adopted by a legal system is,
paradoxically, more and less direct than the case in the first sense. It might
come about in the following way. If a legal system’s rule of recognition5 does not
contain any provision, either expressly stated or implied, making the
satisfaction of some moral standard or another a requirement for the legal
validity of individual rules of law, such that a legal rule properly enacted,
i.e., enacted in accordance with the system’s norms and regulations for
law-making, but which is morally deficient one way or the other, would still be
considered a valid law of the system, then I would consider legal positivism to
have been adopted by the legal system in question.6
This way of adopting legal positivism would be more
direct than the first in the sense that the criteria of legal validity as
contained in the system’s rule of
recognition would be binding on all judges and other officials in the
system, whose business it is to interpret and apply the laws, irrespective of
their personal views on the appropriate relationship between the twin social
institutions of law and morality.
On the other hand, this manner of adopting legal
positivism would be less direct than the first mode of adoption, to the extent
that adopting legal positivism in this way need not be the product of an
internalised intellectual deliberation, or conscious philosophical commitment
by any of the system’s officials, or norm-subjects. In other words, a legal
system could adopt legal positivism in this second sense, even where no jurist
or scholar in it could be said to be a legal positivist in the first sense. The
adoption of legal positivism in the second sense might be based on no more than
the pragmatic consideration that the theory augurs well for the efficient
administration of the law.
It is only in this second sense of adoption that the
Nigerian writers could plausibly consider legal positivism to have been adopted
by the legal systems of modern African states, when they report that legal
positivism is the dominant legal theory in contemporary Africa.7 Taken in the
first sense of the indirect but dominant influence of philosophically committed
jurists and scholars, I should doubt whether there is enough exposure to the
legal positivist philosophy or any other philosophical creed for that matter by
African jurists and practicing lawyers, to leave such deep intellectual
impression on their thought processes as would enable them to consciously
reflect the tenets of such a theory in their work.
The curricula in African law schools and faculties
usually consist almost exclusively of what Karl Lewellyn once described as
bread-and-butter courses8 . Given this
common emphasis on technical legal training, often considered to be of
immediate practical utility to a developing society, it is only to be expected
that there would be but the barest degree of exposure for lawyers in training,
to the tenets of the philosophies and fundamental assumptions which underlie
the practical matters that constitute the contents of law school instruction.
I hasten to note here however, that this practicing
lawyer’s attitude to philosophical questions is by no means peculiar to African
legal practitioners; philosophically sophisticated lawyers tend to be the
exceptions even in the so-called highly developed legal systems. The typical
lawyer’s cynicism about “deep theory” is captured eloquently by Dicey.
Jurisprudence” [Dicey observes] is
a word which stinks in the nostrils of a practising barrister. A jurist is,
they constantly find, a professor whose claim to dogmatize on law in general
lies in the fact that he has made himself master of no one legal system in
particular, whilst his boasted science consists in the enunciation of
platitudes which, if they ought, as he insists, to be law everywhere, cannot in
fact be shown to be law anywhere.9
Stig Stromholm’s observations on the respective
jurisprudential traditions of ancient Greece, and the Roman
Empire are rather apt here. According to Stromholm, if what
prevailed in ancient Greece
could be described as philosophy without law, i.e., all theory no technique,
then what prevailed in the Roman Empire should
be described as law without philosophy, i.e., all technique no theory.10 My
contention is that in many African legal systems too, what we have is law
without philosophy; as it was in the Roman Empire,
all technique, little or no basic theory.
Legal Positivism
The positivist theory of law has had a checkered
career. In almost two centuries of its modern development, it has metamorphosed
through different phases of changes, refinements, and creative modifications. I
shall state, in very broad outlines, the salient elements of three of the more
prominent versions of the theory. The goal of this exposition is to enable us
isolate the common elements in all of these versions, and to get to the
irreducible minimum properties of a positivist conception of law. Against this
common core of the positivist doctrine, I shall compare the interpretations of
it to be found in the works of its African critics.
Imperativist Positivism
The classic statement of a positivist account of the
nature of law is to be found in John Austin’s much analysed imperativist theory
– the notorious command theory of law. Positive law which, in Austin’s view, is law properly and strictly
so called (and which is the only appropriate matter of scientific
jurisprudence), is the command of a sovereign.11 A sovereign,
says Austin, is
a determinate person or group of persons12 who is
rendered habitual obedience - but who does not render any such obedience to any
one - by the bulk of the population of a politically independent society.13 As for the
notion of a command, Austin
analysed it into three elements:14
1. a
wish conceived by a rational being that another rational being shall do or
forebear from doing;
2. an
evil, or, in current parlance, a sanction, to proceed from the commander and to
be incurred by the commanded party, in case the latter fails to comply with the
wish expressed by the former;
3. intimation
of the wish, by words or other signs.
On Austin’s
model of legal positivism, law is made when a sovereign issues a command.
In summary, the principal features of Austin’s theory are these.
1. The
source of the law is in social fact.
2. Law
derives from the sovereign’s express or tacit commands.
3. Sanction
is an indispensable aspect of the law. In other words, it is Austin’s view that a sanctionless law is
something of a contradiction in terms. This has to be so, given the centrality
of the element of sanction in Austin’s
analysis of the notion of command.
4. There
is no necessary connection between law and morality. Or, to express the idea in
a more positive form, law and morality are conceptually separable. This separability thesis would prove to be
the most enduring element of Austinian positivism. Austin himself was
uncompromising on the validity of the separability thesis. His famous battle
cry is the ringing maxim:
The existence of a law is one
thing, its [moral] merit or demerit is another. Whether it be or be not is one
enquiry; whether it be or be not conformable to an assumed [moral] standard, is
a different enquiry. A law, which actually exists, is a law, though we happen
to dislike it, or though it vary from the text, by which we regulate our
approbation and disapprobation.15
Legal Realism
The realist version of legal positivism is the product
of the American realist movement of the 1920s and 1930s. The movement was so
named because most of its leading exponents were legal scholars and jurists
based in North America, specifically in the United States.16 The realists
conceive the law as consisting in the predictions of the decisions (and sundry
pronouncements) of law courts, in cases brought before them for adjudication.
As Justice Holmes famously put it, “the prophecies of what the courts will do
indeed, and nothing more pretentious, are what I mean by the law”.17 Individual
members of the realist movement qualify this basic proposition in different
ways. But these three features of the theory are fairly constant.
1. Law
is a social fact; the law, as the realists are wont to say, is not a brooding
omnipresent in the sky.
2. The
source of the law is judicial decision. Law, in other words, is the end product
of the process of adjudication.
3. Law
and morality are conceptually separable – the separability thesis.
Normative Legal Positivism
The most current version of the positivist theory is
the normative positivist analysis of the nature of law. This version of legal
positivism has its best expositions in the respective writings of Herbert Hart,18 and Hans
Kelsen.19
The normative positivist analysis of the concept of law was developed in
reaction to the unsatisfactory state of the debate in jurisprudence at about
the middle of this century. Having apprehended the unproductive reductionist
tendencies in classical legal positivism of the Austinian kind and theological
natural law of the Thomist and Blackstonian variety respectively, the normative
positivist seeks to forge a middle path between the two extreme positions. The
goal of normative positivism is to construct a legal theory that is basically
positivistic in conception, but which would be sufficiently flexible
conceptually to also account for the normativity of the law.20
For my purposes here, I state the outlines of H.L.A.
Hart’s version of normative positivism. According to Hart, the beginning of
wisdom in the effort to develop an adequate theory of law is to learn to
conceive the law as a form of social rules21 . Hart’s
theory of law could be summarized in the following three propositions.
1. Law
is a social fact.
2. The
paradigm exemplification of the law consists in the union of primary and
secondary “social rules.”22
3. Law
and morality are conceptually separable.
Professor Hart’s articulation of
the substance of the separability thesis is very instructive. According to
Hart, the import of the separability thesis is, “the simple contention that it
is in no sense a necessary truth that laws reproduce or satisfy certain demands
of morality, though in fact they have often done so.”23
Elsewhere Hart analyses the content of the
separability thesis into two disarmingly simple claims:
First, in the absence of an
expressed constitutional or legal provision, it could not follow from the mere
fact that a rule violated standards of morality that it was not a rule of law;
and [second] conversely, it could not follow from the mere fact that a rule was
morally desirable that it was a rule of law.24
A quick review of the three versions of the positivist
theory stated thus far shows that only two theses seem to be common to all of
them, namely, the social fact thesis, and the separability thesis. The import
of the social fact thesis is the claim that the existence of the law is purely
a matter of social fact. The sources of the law are invariably to be sought in
the inner workings of concrete social institutions. The variations between the
different versions of the theory are explainable in terms of the differences in
the specific social institutions each identifies as the source of the law,
i.e., whether it be in the expression of the will of a monarch, or in the enactment
of a modern parliament, or in the decisions of a law court, or in the complex
interplay of social rules of some form.
Most self-confessed positivists and sympathetic
commentators would most probably agree that these two theses constitute the
irreducible core of the positivist creed. There may, however, be slight
disagreements on which of the two theses to accord logical priority. Kent
Greenawalt, for example, is of the opinion that the social fact thesis is
logically prior to the separability thesis. In his view:
if one had to settle on a central
aspect of legal positivism, as a general approach to legal theory that has
existed over time, one would focus on the premise that law is in some important
sense a social fact or set of social facts. Suppositions
about the connections between law and morality and about the nature of judicial
decisions follow from that.25
Similarly, in his topical essay, “Classical Legal
Positivism at Nuremberg”,26 Stanley L.
Paulson claims that “classical legal positivism rests on two fundamental
doctrines, the command doctrine and the doctrine of absolute sovereignty.”27 This means,
again, that the separability thesis is a derivative of those “two fundamental
doctrines”.
These observations about the logical priority of the
social fact thesis are most likely correct. But for analytical purposes it may
be more helpful to reverse the order of things, since all legal positivists are
equally committed to the separability thesis, and since there are important
disagreements among positivists in regard to the determination of the content of
the social fact thesis.
Let us take the separability thesis as a “negative”
principle, it asserts what the law need not be. I suggest that we make this
“negative” principle serve as the indispensable stump of the positivist account
of the nature of law. Different versions of the theory may then be obtained by
grafting onto this conceptual stump a variety of different “positive” theses. Austin’s imperativist
brand of legal positivism, Hart’s normative positivist analysis of the concept
of law, and the predictivist account developed by the American realists, are
three of the well-known examples of such derivable versions of legal
positivism. In the first, the “positive” thesis that law is the command of a
habitually obeyed, legally illimitable sovereign is grafted onto the
separability thesis. In the second, the “positive” thesis that law is
invariably to be conceived as the union of some form of social rules is grafted
onto the separability thesis. In the third, the “positive” thesis that law is
to be distilled from the decisions reached by courts in matters brought before
them is grafted onto the separability thesis. A rich possibility exists for
theorists to graft other logically compatible “positive” theses onto the
separability thesis, to derive yet other versions of legal positivism.
The African Critics’ Understanding of Legal Positivism
Against this background of a theory that has undergone
profound changes in the course of its checkered evolution, and the rich
possibility which, as I have suggested, exists even now to construct new
variations of it, the understanding of the tenets of legal positivism displayed
by many of its African critics is grossly inadequate. For many of these
commentators28
, it is as if the development of the positivist theory had remained frozen at
the point of Austin’s
expositions, in 1832.29
For example, F. U. Okafor, a leading Nigerian critic
of the theory, claims to understand legal positivism as “a theory which
recognizes as valid laws only such enforceable norms as are enacted or
established by the instrument of the state.”30 The
consequence of this conception of law, Okafor claims, is that for the
positivist, “only statute laws are laws indeed, by the mere fact that they have
been posited by an appropriate political authority.”31 In the face
of these conceptual restrictions, Okafor contends, the legal positivist is led
to exclude from the province of jurisprudence, “such fundamental questions as,’
what are the essence of law?’, ‘why is the citizen obliged to obey the law?’,
’what is the nature of a just and unjust law?’, ‘is what is legally wrong also
morally wrong?’.”32
In the same vein, Justice Akinola Aguda, easily one of
Africa’s leading jurists, conceives the
various versions of legal positivism as “theories of the omnipotence of the
sovereign.”33
The Rev. Dr. N. S. S. Iwe has a similar understanding of the tenets of the positivist
theory of law:
By legal positivism, [Iwe writes,]
we mean essentially that attitude of mind and spirit which regards as valid
laws only such enforceable norms formally enacted or established by the
appropriate official political organ. Here only Municipal laws (or Statute
Laws) are laws for they have been formally so posited by the authority. Once a
given norm or proposal has formally and successfully gone through the technical
procedures, of legislation, it automatically acquires the force of law,
independently of all other considerations moral, teleological and practical.
This is the stand of legal positivism and its school of supporters.34
The sole concern of legal positivism, Iwe continues:
is with the law as ‘it is’ and as
‘laid down’ not with what it ought to be. The separation of ethics and
jurisprudence is complete in legal positivism. The legal ’is’ is all that
counts. The legal ‘ought’ is of no consequence and relevance in positivist
jurisprudence. The formal stamp of technical legality on a given norm – not its
ethical contents and qualification – is the criterion of legal validity.35
Taken in its current stage of development and
sophistication – and this is the sense in which any serious-minded contemporary
commentator ought to take it- the interpretations of the positivist doctrine
that we have been quoting from the African writers are grotesque caricatures.
But it is these caricatures that many of these writers claim to be
theoretically inadequate and practically harmful to the peculiar circumstances
of African legal systems. In the next section, I will examine, under two broad
headings, some of the arguments that these critics adduce in support of their
negative conclusions on legal positivism.
THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT AGAINST LEGAL POSITIVISM
Although one finds passing allusions to this line of
thinking in the works of other African critics of legal positivism, the
clearest articulation of the ontological argument for the rejection of legal
positivism was developed by Dr. F.U. Okafor.36 The argument
is based on what he considers to be the unique characteristics of African
ontology and, by extension, the unique characteristics of the social
institutions that evolved from that ontology. In order to understand the
traditional jurisprudence of Africa, Okafor
claims, we must first understand the salient features of African ontology. As
he puts it, “the African legal tradition is a direct outcome of African
ontology.”37
By “African ontology”, Okafor seems to mean nothing more than the African folk
cosmology – the traditional African view of the universal order, and man’s
place in it. As Okafor understands it, “the morphology of African ‘reality’,
their concept of ‘existence’, shows that there is an intimate ontological
relationship between beings.”38 In other
words, African traditional worldview recognizes that there is “active
interaction.a kind of intersubjective communion”, among the various entities
that constitute the universe. The hierarchy of beings, or as he would prefer to
label these entities, “forces”, range, in a descending order of might and
importance, from the divine force, to terrestrial and celestial forces, to
human forces, terminating with vegetable and mineral forces.39 The place of
man is right at the vortex of this cosmic order; to survive, man must harmonise
his own being (or force) with the reality of the other forces that engulf him.40
From this “ontological” base, there developed,
according to Okafor, unique social and political ideas and institutions in Africa. As regards the evolution of the institution of
law in Africa, with which we are here
primarily concerned, Okafor submits that: “From the ontological relationship
among forces, divine and human, animate and inanimate, and from the fact of the
interaction of these forces arise a practical recognition of two main sources
of law – divine and human.”41 On this
model of the traditional African legal system, there is only one vital
criterion of legal validity, namely, that the purported law be intended by its
maker (whether the lawmaker be God or man) to contribute to the maintenance of
the harmony among the various ontological forces. Hence, “the province of African
jurisprudence is .large enough to include divine laws, positive laws, customary
laws, and any other kinds of laws, provided such laws are intended for the
promotion and preservation of the vital force.”42
From this conception of the nature of law, certain
cardinal features of traditional African legal system are said to emerge. The
first is that African laws are not the commands of any sovereign. In the
traditional African political system, Okafor had earlier reported, there would
have been no sovereigns to issue such commands in the first place. “The African
political culture”, he claims, “recognises only leaders and not rulers, seniors
but not superiors.”43
The second characteristic of the traditional African
legal system is the conspicuous lack of emphasis on enforceability. This is
due, again, to the absence of centralised authorities – symbolized, for
example, by the Austinian sovereign – to supervise the enforcement of the laws
of traditional African society. In view of the absence of a law-enforcing
central authority, the African (in traditional times) endeavoured to observe
law and order because of his ontological and moral conviction that a breach of
the law would upset the ontological order44 . And, it
was the general belief of course, that to upset the ontological order was to
provoke calamitous reprisals to fall, not only upon one’s own head, but also
upon the whole community of which one is a member.
The third salient characteristic of the traditional
African legal system is the belief in the existence of a necessary connection
between law and morality. Or, as Okafor puts it, there was the belief “[that]
there cannot be any separation of morality and legality in the African legal
experience.”45
Again, the explanation for this belief in the conceptual union of law and
morality goes back, ultimately, to the ontological undercurrent of the
jurisprudence of traditional Africa. “It is
because African positive laws have ontological foundations that they have ipso facto a moral foundation, for in
African ethical thought, what is considered ontologically good will therefore
be accounted ethically good; and at length be assessed as juridically just.”46 In view of
this jurisprudential heritage, Okafor’s conclusion is that the African legal
system must reject legal positivism in all its ramifications. This, as he says,
is because, “the legal positivists tenets and their corollaries are in complete
opposition to the African ontology and African jurisprudence that depends on
it.”47
The opposition of the positivist philosophy to African
jurisprudence is manifested in several ways. First, legal positivism, says
Okafor, conceives law as the commands of a sovereign ruler, issued to his obedient
subjects. This is clearly opposed to the tenets of African jurisprudence, by
the terms of which the existence of such a sovereign ruler is denied, and where
laws are reportedly conceived as the ordinances of reason. Second, legal
positivism is said to posit enforceability as a necessary condition for the
existence of law. But African jurisprudence denies the necessity of
enforceability. Third, and most important, legal positivism denies that there
is a necessary connection between the validity of a rule of positive law and
the satisfaction of some presumed standards of morality. On the contrary,
African jurisprudence is said to affirm that there is a necessary connection
between morality and the validity of positive law.
It is easy to guess Okafor’s conclusion from all this:
there can be no room for the positivist creed, as far as the development of the
African legal system is concerned. Okafor counsels that “in the African world
serious efforts must be made to ensure that our laws, statutory or customary,
take due cognizance of African ontology. Only a law with such ontological
foundation would be a law of the people for the people.”48
Okafor’s submission is very interesting, at times even
fascinating. Surely he has taken the discourse to hitherto unsuspected realms.
I should doubt, however, whether what is left of Okafor’s case against legal
positivism would stand up to critical scrutiny, once the argument is stripped
of the exotic but largely illusory garb of “African ontology”. Indeed, I will
argue that Okafor’s argument against legal positivism is flawed on all counts:
his description of the traditional jurisprudence of Africa does not correspond
to anything in reality; his interpretation of the legal positivist doctrine –
which he sets the so called African jurisprudence up against – is clearly out
of vogue, outdated perhaps by more than one and a half centuries. I start with
Okafor’s exposition of legal positivism.
Okafor’s understanding of legal positivism goes no
further than the account developed in John Austin’s The Province of Jurisprudence Determined, a monograph, as we have
established above, first published in 1832. The positivist movement in legal
theory has, of course, undergone major transformations since Austin’s time. The transformations have been
especially profound in the works of modern normative positivists. As a result
of these transformations, it is no longer true – assuming that it once ever was
true – that the positivist theory offers a model on which only duly enacted
statutes may qualify as valid laws. On the model of modern legal positivism,
customary laws, positive international laws, and conventional constitutional
law – whatever that may mean – may now qualify as valid laws of a municipal
legal system, i.e., provided that such norms are so identified by the system’s rule of recognition. By the same token, all those questions which Okafor
considers to be fundamental, “’what are the essence of law?’, ‘why is the citizen
obliged to obey the law?’, ‘what is the nature of a just and unjust law?’, ‘is
what is legally wrong also morally wrong?’”, now fall squarely within the
province of positivist jurisprudence. In fact, neither Austin nor Bentham, nor
any other positivist of note has ever canvassed the exclusion of these
questions from the province of jurisprudence. By limiting the survey of what he
touts as “the genesis and development of legal positivism”49 to its most
reductionistic form in the writings of John Austin, Okafor’s exposition can be
said to exhibit what Olufemi Taiwo has described as “a serious deficiency in
scholarship.”50
Let us turn our critical attention to Okafor’s
description of the traditional jurisprudence of Africa.
My contention is that there is no one such thing; there has never been one such
thing. Here again, Taiwo has said much that needs to be said about the
fictional character of Okafor’s portrayal of a philosophy of law indigenous to
the whole of Africa, quite eloquently. Simply put, the African continent has
always been too culturally diverse and heterogeneous for anything remotely
approximating to a dominant legal philosophy, identifiable with the whole
continent, to have emerged. As Taiwo rightly observed, “to collapse all of Africa’s diverse socio-political and legal traditions
into one, which prevailed over all the areas, is to mistake the common occupation
of a geographical continuum for social consensus.”51
There is a second and equally significant sense in
which Okafor’s descriptions fail to capture the current realities of African
socio-political ideas and institutions: it ignores the fact of centuries of
exposure by African societies to profound cultural influences from other lands.
Surely it would be difficult to ascertain what remains as the culturally pure
and unadulterated African in a social or political idea or institution in a
typical modern African society, once we reckon with how such an idea or
institution must have been shaped in some way, by the “corrupting” influences
of European colonialism, and before European colonialism, by the “corrupting”
influences of Arabo- Islamic cultures.
Of course no one wants to suggest that these cultural
influences have been mono- directional, Arab to Africa,
or, Europe to Africa.
What we here refute is the suggestion by Okafor and the other purveyors of this
naïve cultural irredentism, that if we can only search long enough in our
cultural archives we will somehow uncover some elements of our cultural past
that have been left pure and untainted by alien influences.
Okafor’s mistake, in the first instance, is to have
generalized from the socio- political set up of his own native Igbo society, in
Eastern Nigeria, to the whole of Africa. But whereas ethnographic accounts confirm that
the social and political arrangement of traditional Igbo society was based on
the age-grade system, thus indicating that the Igbo society of old might indeed
have recognized “only leaders and not rulers, seniors but not superiors”, there
are likewise conclusive historical records to confirm that in other parts of the
continent, kings and emperors reigned, whose law-making powers and competence
rivaled those of any monarch in Medieval Europe.
Also to be noted, on a second count, is the historical
fact that the social and political structure of indigenous Igbo society has
since been profoundly altered, thanks to the activities of the colonizing
British authorities, who created the institution of paramount rulers—the so
called Warrant Chiefs—in Igboland. The purpose then was to replicate the
economic successes and administrative efficiency of indirect rule, which the British had employed in Northern and Western Nigeria, societies where large kingdoms and
empires had long evolved, complete with sophisticated political systems. As a
result of that (entirely self-serving) innovation by the British, Eastern Nigeria of today can boast of a whole range of
paramount rulers. Okafor’s description is, therefore, not only a monument to
hasty generalisation, it is also anachronistic, that is, even if we restrict
its scope to Igbo society.
For our purposes here, there would seem to be no use
in subjecting this argument to further scrutiny. Its defects are obvious. To
set up what must amount to a caricature of legal positivism – as the doctrine
has been developed in recent decades – against the model of some mythical
African jurisprudence, has as much credibility as the activities of an agent,
who, having first toiled very hard to erect a strawman proceeds at once to
attack it vigorously.
But before I conclude this examination of Okafor’s
ontological argument for the rejection of legal positivism, there is one
important though unstated assumption in the argument that deserves to be
closely examined. That assumption would be philosophically significant – if it
turns out to be true – even if the objections that I have been raising against
the other premises of the argument are sound and conclusive. The assumption is
that the African ontology and the traditional African legal philosophy that is
based on it describe the model of a world that is worth “returning” to. We
shall notice that the mere fact—assuming it is a fact—that the legal positivist
creed is in “complete opposition” to the tenets of African jurisprudence would
not, in itself, constitute a sufficient reason for rejecting legal positivism.
What would amount to a sufficient reason for that purpose is a conjunction of
that supposed fact with the truth of another proposition, namely, that the
African conception of law is a better theory of the nature of law. Supposedly,
in Okafor’s view, that would be because African jurisprudence is predicated on
the soundest ontological theory, or an ontological theory that is, at least,
superior to its presumed counterpart from the western world.
Let us look then more closely into the structure and
contents of the “traditional African world”, which in my view, would seem to
correspond to Okafor’s description of the African ontology. For even if it is
the case, as I have argued, that the portrait fails to capture anything real,
and even if it is the case, as I have argued, that Okafor’s interpretation of
legal positivism is an outdated caricature, his description of the African
ontology and the resultant African jurisprudence may yet present the picture of
an ideal condition which is superior to what would amount to a true
representation of legal positivism. And in that case, of course, that ideal
condition would be worth striving to attain.
The picture that seems, in my view, to emerge from
Okafor’s descriptions is that of a very simple social order, with all but the
barest rudiments of political organization. Scientifically, this has to be an
utterly simple world: chances are that in that world, explanations, no matter
how mundane or common-place the phenomenon being explained, would invariably
implicate the personal dispositions of some god, ancestral spirit, or one of a
myriad of other supernatural agents.
In such a world and given its aboriginal conception of
law, it should not surprise us if we are told that the law of gravity readily
qualifies for inclusion in the province of jurisprudence (surely the law of
gravity contributes to the maintenance of harmony among the various life
forces), whereas many a law that we may design to regulate modern commerce
might fail to make it into the province of jurisprudence. This is, after all, a
world in which morality and religion are conceived to be inseparable, and where
no law is to be considered valid unless religion and morality sanction it. It
would be a world, in short, in which as far as legal conceptions go, the
institutions of morality, religion, and law are conceived as woven into an
inseparable, tangled mesh. Even Austin’s crude imperativism would be far
superior to that jurisprudence.
Clearly, an ontology like that and the social and
political ideas and institutions that might sprout from it do not present the
modern African, or, for that matter, any one from any part of the modern world,
with the model of an ideal world worth striving to attain. Nor should we be
surprised at our abhorrence at what we conjecture might be the state of that
world. To the extent that the portrait corresponds to any reality at all, it
can only correspond to a state of the rudimentary social order in which
humanity once existed, not only on the continent of Africa but in all parts of
the globe, when earthly civilization was at its earliest infancy. Having
transcended that condition for millennia, for the vast majority of human
communities in all parts of the contemporary world, the only surviving
evidences of such a past are marks on the walls of ancient caves. This is no
less the case for African societies. Indeed, had someone, not “a native son”
like Okafor or myself, but say, a foreign social scientist, presented us with
that picture of an Africa in some immediate past (say, a hundred or two hundred
years before the onset of colonialism), we would all, quite rightfully, have
protested vigorously. We would have countered his descriptions with
overwhelming historical evidence, confirming that great empires had existed and
flourished all over the continent, for thousands of years before the advent of
colonialism. Now suppose that not content with presenting his unflattery
descriptions as mere conjectural reconstruction, our foreign social scientist
informs us that he had also reached the normative conclusion that it would be
better for the modern African to organize his society on the model of that
simple past. Smelling the dirty hands of racism at work, and feeling gravely
insulted, we Africans would, no doubt, have called for his head.
Okafor’s idea of “the African ontology” belongs, I
suppose, within the genre of ethno-philosophy. In general the ethno-philosophy
project has not done too well; some would rate it an outright conceptual flop.
Ethno-legal-philosophy is not likely to fare any better. This pessimistic
conclusion on the viability of ethno-philosophy as a general methodology, and
ethno-legal-philosophy in particular should, however, not be misconstrued as
indicating a wholesale rejection of all attempts to probe into, and as far as
possible, to reconstruct the past. My position is not borne out of any form of
naïve triumphalist modernism. By no means do I advocate an unqualified
celebration of everything new and modern, nor do I want to suggest that Africa
should ignore her past. Quite apart from the fact that history will not be so
wantonly ignored for long, I do strongly believe that there may be a lot of
valuable socio- political ideas from Africa’s past, which when carefully
extricated from the debris of ancient superstitions, can profitably be
appropriated for modern use.
To take a concrete example, Dr. T. O. Elias has shown,
quite persuasively, why a preoccupation with imprisonment as a way of
dispensing criminal justice may not sit well with African customary legal
practice. Elias points out that to the extent that “punishment of the offender
and a corresponding satisfaction of the offended are two distinct questions
that must be faced if real justice is to be achieved,”52 then
pre-colonial African customary legal practices may have struck a more useful
balance between these two requirements of justice.
While viewing the matter of punishment of offenders
with grim seriousness, African customary legal practices have tended to put an
equal or greater emphasis on the side of the need for restitution. From the
point of view of the kinsmen of a victim of manslaughter, it is equally, if not
more important, that the murderer be made to pay them “blood- money”, before he
is sent to jail or executed. Hence the African under the colonial legal system
was understandably appalled when offenders were “merely” imprisoned by the
colonial authorities, without anything said or done about the need to make
restitution to victims or to a victim’s family:
When a person has been found guilty
of, for example, manslaughter of another and is thrown into gaol without at the
same time being made to pay the blood-money to his victim’s surviving relations
as required by customary law, not only such deprived relatives but also the
general public are infuriated by the procedure. Imprisonment benefits the
British Government by thus providing it with another servant, while it does
nothing to assuage the personal grief or satisfy the legal expectations of the
bereaved family.53
This perceived need to take the matter of restitution
as seriously as we take society’s need for punishment suggests, in my view,
that there is an urgent need to take a closer look at the procedures for the
administration of criminal justice as presently constituted in the legal
systems of modern African states. In view of the apparent lack of sufficient
awareness of the requirements of the different forms of laws under which an
injured party may seek remedy by the majority of the citizens of African
states, it may be desirable to mitigate the rigid distinction, inherited from
colonial legal systems, between civil and criminal procedures.
We must, however, append a couple of caveats to all of this. The validity of
Dr. Elias’s observations concerning the customary emphasis on some form of
restitution, e.g., payment of blood-money, is most likely limited to certain
regions of the African continent, and even in those regions, true only of
certain historical points in time. This takes nothing away from Elias’s
otherwise excellent, pioneering study of African customary law. He cannot have
claimed, without concrete empirical evidence, that payment of blood-money (or
any other form of restitution for that matter) was a practice universally
engaged in by all traditional African societies. Nor can he claim, in the face
of what seem to be strong evidence to the contrary, that the average Yoruba man
at the commencement of the twenty-first century nurses a sense of loss at not
being paid blood-money, as vividly as his ancestors might once have done.
Second, there is all the evidence to show that
Africans under colonial rule were not alone in been “piqued”, as Dr. Elias put
it, by the relative indifference of the British criminal justice system at that
time, to the need to extract restitution from offenders in addition to, or, as
a way of punishing them. Reform-minded philosophers and social critics, led by
Jeremy Bentham54
had directed critical attention to this unsatisfactory aspect of the British
legal system, as early as the beginning of the nineteenth century, or earlier.
If a man were to willfully set fire to his neighbour’s
house or farm, the penalty under British colonial law would be a term of
imprisonment. Partly this would be retribution; partly it would be imposed to
serve as deterrence to other potential arsonists. Bentham is however of the
view that justice would be better served if the offender was fined a certain
sum, to be paid over to his victim. In Bentham’s view, “the best fund whence
satisfaction can be drawn is the property of the delinquent, since it then
performs with superior convenience the functions both of satisfaction and
punishment.”55
On this view, it would be “juster and simpler” to auction off an arsonist’s
house, farm or automobile, and remedy the victim’s distress and loss from the
proceeds.
Bentham is willing to go several steps further by way
of securing just restitution. For instance, in the case of an impecunious
offender, Bentham proposes that funds should be drawn from the public treasury
to make good the victim’s loss: “But if the offender is without property, ought
the injured party to remain without satisfaction? No, for satisfaction is almost as necessary as punishment. It ought to be furnished out of the public treasury,
because it is an object of public good, and the security of all is interested
in it.”56
I have entered these caveats at length to caution us
on the ever present dangers of cross- cultural and cross-epochal generalisations,
as well as to counter the dubious suggestion which some cultural romantics
promote, that we shortchange our ancestors if we do not claim some items of
wisdom and insights into the dynamics of social organizations, as their
exclusive preserve. African peoples, in the past and at present, are not
different from the rest of humanity in the possession and exercise of innate
powers of philosophical reflection, and in being endowed with a healthy dose of
common sense. But then what sane person has ever denied that?
I conclude this section by noting that in the effort
to see what can be salvaged from the legal systems and practices of indigenous
African societies, legal philosophers in particular and jurists in general will
do well to consult the various writings of cultural anthropologists who studied
those aspects of our cultural past. The excellent bibliographical references at
the end of Dr. Elias’s equally excellent monograph on The Nature of African Customary Law, is a good place to start.
The Moral Argument
The next line of objection to legal positivism is not
one distinct argument as such. It is a cluster of overlapping complaints about
some alleged pernicious effects of the positivist doctrine, when observed in
practice. Among the morally undesirable results that critics have claimed to
notice when they observe the positivist doctrine in practice are the following:
1. that
it encourages tyranny by allowing undue and excessive powers to government
officials. As J.M. Elegido put it, “.positivist approaches in law tend to do
great harm, especially in so far as of themselves they tend to legitimate the
actions of whoever finds himself in power;”57
2. that
it is a bad theory of legislation;58
3. that
it is a bad theory of adjudication.59
4. The
cumulative effect of (i), (ii), and (iii), critics have concluded, is that when
the positivist doctrine is put into practice, it helps to create a social and
political environment that is hostile to the exercise and defense of human
rights.
Now, anyone with a passing acquaintance with the
literature on legal philosophy would readily see that these are fairly standard
objections to the positivist theory. One is therefore tempted to dispose of
them by drawing from the stock of standard positivist rejoinders, which, in my
opinion, are quite adequate. We must resist that temptation. First, we have to
find out what else the African critics of the positivist creed have in mind by
raising these well-worn allegations anew.
The idea seems to be that there are some uniquely
African reasons for recycling these objections at this time. Justice Akinola
Aguda provided the clearest statement of such a reason. I quote him in full:
What has become of grave importance
to us in Africa – but here I shall confine myself to Nigeria – is that the
emergence of military and dictatorial governments in this continent has brought
the positivist theories into focus, and caused alarm not only in the minds of
progressive jurists but also in the minds of the general public. England and
some other European countries at least since after the Second World War have
been able to contain the positivist concept of law, thanks to inbuilt and
highly developed democratic practices. Here in Nigeria no such practices have
ever been permitted to germinate, not to talk of grow; hence we have not been
able to curtail the evils of positivist thinking on law which most lawyers – in
this I include judges of all grades – have imbibed from the commencement of
their training in the law Faculties.60
The import of Justice Aguda’s submission is clear
enough: what makes legal positivism so morally harmful when put into practice
in an African society – like Nigeria – is the absence, in the African
socio-political environment, of inbuilt and highly developed democratic
institutions and practices. It is as if legal positivism were a variety of
plant, to draw an analogy with botanical processes, nurtured in the
democratically fertile climates of Western Europe, and North America, this
plant is thoroughly domesticated; it bears succulent fruits. Transplanted onto
the harsh and rocky terrain of political dictatorship and tyranny in Africa, it
becomes a man-eating weed. Now, what are we to make of this argument?
To begin with, we should note that to date, critics
have not come up with any independent argument to show that legal positivism is
a bad theory in itself. Often, critics have had to concede, as we find Justice
Aguda conceding in the passage quoted above, that the positivist philosophy
does not produce the morally objectionable consequences that they claim to
result from its application in African legal systems elsewhere.
Perhaps the critics’ point is not that legal
positivism is a morally evil doctrine in itself; the allegation may be that the
evils that the critics complain about result when subscription to the
positivist creed is combined with the absence of sufficiently developed
democratic institutions and practices. That much is clear from the line of
reasoning quoted from Justice Aguda above, when he contrasts what he takes to
be the morally pernicious effects of legal positivism in Africa to its benign
effects in the operations of the legal systems of the industrialised
democracies of Western Europe. The next step in this anti- positivist position
is usually the suggestion that the moral evils complained about would not
result if , instead of the positivist creed, the legal systems of African
states under one form of dictatorship or another had subscribed to the
alternative natural law philosophy.
The problem with the first part of this argument is
that it may have put the blame where it does not belong. It seems most likely
that the critic here confuses the breakdown of the political process for a
failure of legal theory. I would have thought that it is more reasonable to
blame the dictatorial tendencies in African governments and the resultant evils
of political corruption and human rights abuses, on the frequent disruptions of
the political process—usually, through military incursion into civil
governance—which has so far prevented democracy from flourishing, and not on
the positivist creed in legal theory. Surely, no one would suggest, with any
degree of seriousness, that the positivist conception of law is to be held
causally responsible for the absence of “inbuilt and highly developed”
democratic institutions and practices in post independence African states.
For parallel reasons, I should doubt whether
subscription to the natural law philosophy would be sufficient in itself, to
curtail the occurrences of the moral evils of gross abuses of political
offices, misuse of power, and violation of human rights, in a fundamentally
undemocratic polity. Indeed, the natural law doctrine is the most vulnerable to
use and abuse by just about anyone with a political agenda. Anarchists,
reactionaries, liberal democrats, as well as libertarian minimalists, have all
been known to invoke the principles of natural law to justify their respective
causes.
Professor Alf Ross likened the natural law doctrine to
a conceptual harlot, whose services are readily available to all manners of
political ideologies. Hence, as Ross put it, “from a practical-political point
of view.naturalistic theories have been conservative as well as evolutionary
and revolutionary. In the province of political philosophy all the political
systems from extreme absolutism to direct democracy have been vindicated by
natural law philosophies.”61 It does
seem, therefore, that to base the hope for democracy and the aspirations of
human rights on the natural law philosophy is like building a magnificent
castle on a pile of shifting sand.
Often in their haste to condemn legal positivism,
critics tend to confuse a number of issues that should be separated and
carefully analysed. They have thus been led through such series of conceptual
muddles to proclaim what, under closer analysis, turn out to be patently false
allegations against the theory. For example, the impression is sometimes
created that the legal positivist does not have the resources within the
framework of his theory to draw the vital distinction between a lawful order
and a regime of mere brute force. The imputation of such a crude theory of
legal validity, according to which positivists are held to equate a regime of
law to the gunman situation writ-large, is exemplified by the passage quoted
from Dr. Elegido above, where he asserts that one major way in which positivist
approaches in legal theory do great harm is “.especially in so far as of themselves
they tend to legitimate the actions of whoever finds himself in power.”62
It takes only one moment for us to realise that if
this allegation were true, it would be especially damaging to the credibility
of the positivist theory in the African context. Most of the moral atrocities
that people complain about were committed under undemocratic, dictatorial
governments. In almost all the cases, those governments were military dictatorships;
the regimes were often led by bands of military officers, who, after violently
overthrowing a lawful government would proclaim the suspension of the legal
basis of the democratic constitution, and subsequently proceed to govern by
issuing decrees. The pertinent question is whether such military decrees
qualify as valid laws.
The critic seems to suppose that the legal positivist
would, willy-nilly, and without any further explanation or argument, return an
affirmative answer to that question. Of course that supposition is wrong. It is
in fact contradicted by overwhelming textual evidence from contemporary
positivist writings. Since this crude conception of legal validity is an
account which most modern legal positivists expressly reject, even if the account
may, with some argument, be attributed to old-style reductionist legal
positivism, it cannot be attributed to the positivist creed as a whole. Modern
normative positivists in particular reject that gunman situation writ-large
view of legal validity, along with other indefensible elements of Austinian
positivism. According to H. L. A. Hart:
The root cause of the failure of
[Austinian legal positivism] is that the elements out of which the theory was
constructed, viz. The ideas of orders, obedience, habits, and threats, do not
include, and cannot by their combination yield, the idea of a rule, without
which we cannot hope to elucidate even the most elementary forms of laws.63
I can see no basis for attributing to a theorist, who
proposes that the concept of law be elucidated in terms of social rules, the
simple imperativist model, according to which there may be nothing more to a
regime of law than the gunman situation writ-large. In the same vein, I can see
no justification at all for the critic’s supposition that legal positivists
would, without any further ado, accept the decrees issuing from the
headquarters of a military junta as valid laws.
The critic might point out that Hart equivocates a lot
on the concept of a social rule. As many commentators have pointed out, it is
clear that by the time Hart developed his account of the existence of a legal
system (as distinct from the validity of individual rules within a legal
system), i.e., Hart’s two minimum necessary and sufficient conditions for the
existence of a legal system, the notion of social rules that goes into the
analysis is radically different from the idea of customary social rules,
introduced in the early chapters of The
Concept of Law, which owe their existence to wide-spread acceptance in the
relevant society. Given this equivocation, the critic might press on, Hart’s
normative legal positivism can offer no theory of legal validity that is
qualitatively different from what is contained in John Austin’s imperativist
model.
This is no doubt a very strong objection against
Hart’s positivist theory of law. But, as I have argued elsewhere,64 the
objection does not hold against all Hartian positivist theories. In any case,
my view is that legal positivists need to be more explicit in their explanation
of the moral legitimacy of the foundation of a legal system. Observing that
while Hart’s minimum requirements may be necessary, they would not be
sufficient to constitute the foundation of a legal system, I have proposed
that: “In order for the enactment by officials to amount to valid laws (given
that a valid rule of law has the inherent potential to generate the moral
obligation to comply with its requirement) the process whereby persons get to
become lawgivers and remain lawgivers, must be a morally legitimate one.”65
The critic’s response might be to welcome this
proposal, and then to gleefully proclaim that the underlying theory can no
longer be a true variant of legal positivism. As usual, the critic would have
been celebrating a bit too soon; his observation is wrong. While my proposal
addresses the issue of the moral foundation of a legal system as a whole, it
says nothing yet about the moral content of individual rules of law to be made
by officials with the requisite moral authority, subsequent to the constitution
of a morally legitimate legal system. On that latter question, I firmly uphold
the separability thesis.
Going back then to the question we posed above: are
the decrees issued by military regimes valid laws? My inclination is to return
a negative answer. For how can anything lawful result from such fundamental
illegality that military regimes often represent? But this answer would have to
be further supported by arguments, for it clearly runs up against the received
opinion on the matter. The received opinion is backed by much of existing
international law, according to which the foundations of a legal system—the
Kelsenian grundnorm—is deemed to be
changeable by the incidence of a “revolution”.
In the Cold War decades, during which time,
coincidentally, military juntas were running amok all over Africa and in other
parts of the developing world, public international law treated military coups
d’etat as satisfying the definition of grundnorm-
changing “revolution”. Therefore, the recognition accorded to successive
military regimes in Nigeria and elsewhere in Africa, both by the municipal
courts and the international community, was not necessitated by our legal
systems’ subscription to the positivist creed in legal theory; it was
facilitated by the exigencies of international politics.
Other than this crucial distinction between the
existence conditions of a legal system and the criteria of validity of
individual rules of law, another important distinction which critics of legal
positivism often fail to draw is that between the determination of the validity
of a rule of law and the determination of its moral bindingness, i.e.,
determining whether or not a norm- subject lies under a moral obligation to
comply with the provisions of the (valid) rule. Positivists are often treated
as if they hold the view that the process of ascertaining the validity of a law
is identical to the process of ascertaining whether or not there arises a moral
obligation to obey it. But unless a positivist fails to pay attention to what
he is doing, he cannot fall into that error.
Acutely aware of their endorsement of the separability
thesis, modern positivists have often made it clear that the mere fact that a
rule is legally valid does not, by any means, automatically translate to the
generation of a moral obligation on the citizen to comply with it. Legal
positivists know all too well that a law may be valid but too unjust or
otherwise too immoral for there to be a moral obligation to obey it. Bentham’s
teaching is for a clear boundary to be drawn between “expository” jurisprudence
and “censorial” jurisprudence. His admonition to the norm-subject is to obey
promptly but to criticize freely. That Benthamite dichotomy still animates much
of modern positivist writing, perhaps with the enlightened modification
shifting the emphasis from prompt obedience to free censoring. Leading legal
positivists are at the forefront of the enlightened liberalism of our age, just
as Bentham and his disciples were the apostles of liberal reforms in their
time.
The allegation was once made that the vulgarized
reformulation of the separability thesis, “law is law” (Gesetz als Gesetz) may have served as the doctrinal shroud that
blocked the moral vision of the courts in Nazi Germany. Professor Hart’s
response is that that attitude toward the law is not dictated by the logic of
the positivist doctrine. Thus, next time someone comes around to recite that
piece of platitude, “law is law”, the correct response is to remind him that
his platitude tells only half of the story: “the truly liberal answer to any
sinister use of the slogan “law is law” or the distinction between law and
morals is, “very well, but that does not conclude the question. Law is not
morality; do not let it supplant morality.”66
Some critics would insist that even if legal
positivism may not be directly implicated in the enthronement of a dictatorial
regime, it nonetheless help such regimes to consolidate and to go about
executing their immoral objectives with relative ease, using the
instrumentality of the judiciary. Olufemi Taiwo, for example, alluded to “.how
legal positivism might have made it easier for judges to escape censure for
their roles under, say Idi Amin in Uganda or Ian Smith in Zimbabwe (then Rhodesia).”67 Taiwo’s
further allusion to “unimaginative squirming judges [wanting] to hide under the
veneer of having no control of their pronouncements”, suggests that what he
implies here is that a courageous, morally upright and resourceful judge
operating under such a fascist regime should be able to ensure that his
judicial decisions do not result in blatant injustice or undeserved human
suffering. Taiwo seems to believe that a judge with these qualities would be
able to frustrate the evil designs and programmes of tyrants like Idi Ami, Ian
Smith, Sani Abacha, Mobutu Sese Seko, etc., to the extent that the tyrant
attempts to accomplish his evil ends through the legal process (or what at the
point in time passes as the legal process). The unstated assumption in Taiwo’s
argument and other versions of the objection by opponents of legal positivism,
is that subscription to the positivist philosophy rubs a judge of the virtues
of courage, moral uprightness, and resourcefulness.
It is of course difficult to see how this might be so;
and Taiwo fails to provide any detailed explanation of the presumed process
whereby the positivist philosophy turns judges—who are otherwise virtuous men
and women—into moral cretins. In my view, subscription to the positivist
doctrine should not in itself prevent a judge from attempting to rig the
outcome of a judicial decision to suit his own moral convictions. Legal
positivism is not antithetical to judicial activism. Judicial activism is,
however, a double- edged sword, it can cut both ways. Just as a judge whose
morality we agree with might (under the banner of judicial activism) manipulate
the interpretation of a legal provision, to obtain a morally agreeable result, so
too might another judge, whose moral standards we disagree with, manipulate the
interpretations of a rule to arrive at a morally disagreeable verdict.
Our experience in the recent past would indicate that
the two kinds of judges are easy to find in the Nigerian judiciary. In the
system where we had a high court judge with enough courage and moral rectitude
to declare the so called Interim National Government (ING)—set up after the
annulment of the June 1993 presidential elections—illegal, we also had another
high court judge, who, under the cover of darkness at night, rendered the
momentous verdict upholding the lawfulness of the so called Association for
Better Nigeria’s (ABN) prayer to have the presidential elections of June 12,
1993 stopped. I doubt whether Justice (Mrs.) Akinsanya, the judge at the Lagos
high court was any less a legal positivist’ or, positivist-inspired than
Justice (Mrs.) Ikpeme, who gave the infamous ABN ruling at the Abuja high
court.
In extreme cases, the professionally proper thing for
a judge to do may be to resign his appointment, i.e., instead of returning a
morally unjust verdict, or trying to tinker with the clear meanings of the law.
The morally proper thing for any person to do is to join in the campaign
against an evil regime. Depending on the severity of the atrocities being
committed by the regime, and an overall estimate of the circumstance, such
campaigns may range from peaceful civil protests to a resort to armed
confrontation.
In the years immediately preceding the end of the
Second World War, some suggestions were heard from certain scholarly circles to
the effect that legal positivism may have contributed to paving the way for the
enthronement and sustenance of the Nazi ideology in Germany – suggestions quite
similar to the accusations now been leveled against the positivist creed by its
African critics. Professor Hart’s rejoinder to those allegations of possible
positivist complicity in Nazis’ reign of terror is most instructive. It is that
rather than blaming the alleged “insensitiveness to the demands of morality and
subservience to state power in a people like the Germans” on the positivist
creed in legal theory, attempts should be made to discover the origins of such
beliefs and dispositions in the German society. As Hart put it:
There is an extraordinary naivete
in the view that insensitiveness to the demands of morality and subservience to
state power in a people like the Germans should have arisen from the belief
that law might be law though it failed to conform with the minimum requirement
of morality. Rather this terrible history of insensitiveness to the demands of
morality and subservience to state power prompts inquiry into why emphasis on
the slogan “law is law:, and the distinction between law and morals, acquired a
sinister character in Germany, but elsewhere, as with the utilitarians
themselves, went along with the most enlightened liberal attitudes.68
Borrowing a leaf from Hart, I would admonish the
African critics of legal positivism to commence inquiries into why democratic
institutions and practices “have never been permitted to germinate, not to talk
of grow”, as Justice Aguda put it, in these African societies, instead of
laying the responsibility for the social and moral evils of political
dictatorship at the door step of the positivist theory.
An African Case For Legal Positivism
Philip Soper69 has argued
that the choice of a legal theory cannot be based on moral considerations. In
other words, Soper is of the view that it would make no moral difference at
all, whether one chooses legal positivism or its rival, the natural law theory.
I doubt whether this is indeed the case, although I have no intention of
defending a substantive position here. But even if one may not choose a legal
theory for moral reasons, it would not follow that we may not prefer one legal
theory to another, for reasons that are not any less compelling. Presently, I
shall argue for the position that there are compelling pragmatic reasons for
the legal systems of modern African states to choose the positivist theory of
law, in preference to the natural law theory.
For our purposes here, we shall take the core element
of a positivist conception of law as consisting in the affirmation of the
separability thesis. On the other hand, we take the core element of a natural
law theory to be the denial of the separability thesis. My contention is that
faced with the choice between legal positivism on one hand and natural law
theory on the other, there are strong historical and pragmatic reasons for the
legal systems of modern nation states in Africa to choose the positivist
doctrine.
Earlier on, in section IV.1 of the essay, I criticized
Okafor’s characterisation of what he calls African traditional society on the
grounds, inter alia, that the account
fails to take due cognizance of the enormous cultural diversity that was the
hallmark of the African continent, even in traditional times. My case for the
adoption of legal positivism by modern African states tracks on these facts of
cultural diversity in traditional (or pre-colonial) Africa, conjoined with the
unique colonial experiences, and the resultant post- independence ethnic and
ethical composition of many African nation states at present.
It is a fact that many of the entities that pass for
sovereign nation states in present day Africa are conglomerations of many
different ethnic nationalities, who were arbitrarily lumped together by the
colonial powers. The colonialists had magnified, or underplayed the differences
between these ethno-national groups, as it suited colonial administrative
convenience. Upon the departure of the colonial powers, leaders of the various
ethno-national groups thus “united” for colonial administration had proclaimed
the geographical areas covered by the territories of their different groups as
independent sovereign states. But the elements of cultural diversity that
characterized pre-colonial African societies have survived in the new nation
states. The cultural differences are manifested in the various aspects of life,
in different institutional structures and social practices, ranging from the
most sacred—religious beliefs—to the most mundane, say, attitude toward
commerce.
Nigeria, where many of these African critics of legal
positivism and I come from, offers a particularly rich example of such a great
diversity of ethno-national groups arbitrarily lumped together by the colonial
rulers, and in which the constituent ethnic groups have retained (indeed have
been jealously guiding) their respective cultural identities, after the whole
territory was declared an independent nation state in 1960.
There are close to three hundred natural languages in
Nigeria – and that is not counting the many dialects of each. The majority of
the population is unable to communicate in English, the language of the
departed colonial power and the country’s official language at present. Talking
of religious creeds, Islam is the religion of the North, the Roman Catholic
church is dominant in the East, Islam and Protestant Christianity co-exist in
the West. There are, of course pockets of believers in various indigenous
African religions in all the regions. Each of the major religious sects boasts
of a dizzying array of sub-sects, ranging from extreme orthodoxy or
fundamentalism to permissive liberalism, analogous, one might say, to the
varied dialects of the natural languages. Added to these are a host of other
cultural differences which, as I remarked above, are reflected in matters
ranging from beliefs about matrimony and paternal obligations, to beliefs about
the appropriate relationship between rulers and their subjects, to the morality
of interest-charging. Nigeria, one can only conclude, is one spectacular
geographical artefact.
Now consider the conception of law according to the
critic’s idea of what African jurisprudence should be. On that model of
jurisprudence, which they claim to be in accord with the natural law doctrine,
no positive enactment would be considered a valid law if it were in any way
contrary to some assumed moral principle. We shall recall, for example, how
Okafor had insisted that law, morality, and religion are to be held inseparable
on the model of traditional African worldview, and how he had insisted that all
efforts must be made by modern African legal systems to ensure that the laws
faithfully reflect that worldview. If we adopt this natural- law-inspired
constraint on the possible contents of positive laws, we would have to insert a
provision in the Nigerian Constitution, to the effect that no law is to be
deemed valid if it is contrary to moral, and perhaps also religious, standards.
The question then would be, to which or whose moral or religious creed would
the law have to conform? In other words, whose call is the lawmaker to heed,
given the multitude of moral and religious voices presently coexisting within
the Nigerian geo-political space?
In my view, the surest way to frustrate lawmaking, and
consequently to court the perils of anarchy and the disintegration of the
nation, is to impose this kind of constraints on the possible contents of our
positive laws. Therefore, the separability thesis, according to which it would
not be a necessary truth, hence not a necessary requirement, that our positive
laws reproduce or satisfy certain moral or religious principles, will serve us
better. Of course, our lawmakers would be encouraged to ensure that the laws
they enact conform to as much of morality and, wherever possible, as much of
religion, as possible.
Somewhere in his paper, Okafor had issued the warning
that “African positive laws must not be confused with some past atrocious
practices and acts occasioned by past ignorance of the course of nature and
executed with great religious dexterity.”70 I consider
this a most sensible admonition. It has a corollary: atrocities committed in
the name of the law should not be blamed on religion or morality. Atrocities
committed in the name of the law should be carefully investigated, to determine
what “wrong beliefs” motivated them, and to determine where precisely to put
the blame.
Unfortunately, there can be no way to mark the
distinction which Okafor here considers desirable, that is, if we follow him
and his fellow natural law theorists in weaving the different institutions of
law, morality, and religion into one tangled, inseparable (and of course
inoperable) body of dogmas. On the other hand, one of the guiding aims of legal
positivism, cashed out most forcefully in the separability thesis, is to enable
us draw this kind of crucial distinctions. Standing firmly on the moral
pedestal, we can keep a watchful eye on the operations of the positive law.
The objection could be raised that I have
over-emphasized the issue of cultural diversity of the different ethnic
nationalities that compose a typical nation state in post-colonial Africa; and
that I underplayed the elements of cultural uniformity that are always on
display in these societies. Is it not the case, as P.C. Nwakeze has observed,
that “in the midst of the diversity of African cultures, there is striking
cultural uniformity which allows us to talk of ‘African culture’”?71 In any case,
as rational agents, do citizens of modern African states not agree on many
important points of moral values? I suppose we can grant that both of these
questions could be answered in the affirmative. However, I do not see how that
would in any way undermine my conclusion that to impose the kind of moral or
religious constraints on the possible contents of positive law, such as the
critics of legal positivism advocate, would effectively paralyse the making and
or the administration of laws in a country such as ours.
To grant that there are elements of cultural
uniformity is not in any way to retreat from the observation that there are
also elements of cultural diversity among the various ethno- national groups in
modern African states. To concede that citizens of African states would agree
on many important points of moral values is, likewise, compatible with the
rival observation that those same citizens, informed by different religious and
ethical beliefs, might disagree on many important points of moral and religious
values. My contention is that where such areas of moral and religious
differences are sufficiently fundamental, as I think they would be in any
society as culturally diverse as a typical modern African nation state, they
will frustrate efforts at making and administering laws, should there be moral
or religious constraints on the possible contents of the law, such as the
natural-law-inspired writers would propose.
It will not help much either, to say that the positive
laws be required to conform only to the standards of critical morality. That
suggestion presupposes that there is always agreement as to what these
standards are. That presupposition is wrong. It is easy enough, I suppose, to
expressly incorporate into the letters and principles of our positive laws,
moral or religious values about which there is widespread agreement in the
society.
References
Ajisafe, A. K. Laws and Customs of the Yorruba People.
London: Routledge, 1924.
Austin, John. The Province of Jurisprudence Determineed,
edited by H. L. A. Hart. London: Weidenfeld &Nicolson, 1968.
Bix, Brian (ed.), Analyzing Law: New Essays in Legal Theory.
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998.
Danquah, J. B. Akan Laws and Customs. London: Routledge
&Sons Ltd., 1928.
Dworkin, Ronald. Taking Rights Seriously. Cambridge, Mas:
Harvard University Press, 1977.
Elegido, J. M. Jurisprudence. Ibadan: Spectrum Law
Publishing, 1994.
Elias, T. O. The Nature of African Customary Law.
Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1956.
Elias, T.O. Groundwork of Nigerian Law. London:
Routledge &Kegan Paul, 1954.
Feinberg, Joel.
And Gross, Hyman (ed.), Philosophy of Law.
Belmont, California: Wadsworth Publishing Co. 1980.
Finnis, John. Natural Law and Natural Rights. Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1980.
Gavison, Ruth
(ed.), Issues in Contemporary Legal
Philosophy: The Influence of H.L.A. Hart. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1987.
Guest, Stephen
(ed.), Positivism Today. Aldershot:
Dartmouth Publishing Co. Ltd., 1996.
Hart, H. L. A. The Concept of Law. Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1961.
Kelsen, Hans. The Pure Theory of Law; translated by
Max Knight. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1967.
Morrison, Wayne. Juriprudence from the Greeks to
Post-Modernism. London: Cavendish Publishing Ltd., 1997.
Patterson, Dennis
(ed.), A Companion to Philosophy of Law
and Legal Theory. Cambridge, Mas: Blackwell Publishers Ltd., 1996.
Paulson, Stanley
L. and Paulson Bonnie Litschewski (ed.), Normativity
and Norms: Critical Perspectives on Kelsenian Themes. Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1998.
Raz, Joseph. The Authority of Law. Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1979.
Robert P. George,
(ed.), The Autonomy of Law: Essays on
Legal Positivism. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996.
Sebok, Anthony J. Legal Positivism in American Jurisprudence.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
Shapiro, Ian and
DeCew, Judith Wagner (ed.), Theory and
Practice. New York: New York University Press, 1995.
Simpson, A. W. B.
(ed.), Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence,
(second series). Oxford; Clarendon Press, 1973.
Soper, Philip. A Theory of Law. Cambridge, Mas: Harvard
University Press, 1984.
Waluchow, W. J. Inclusive Positivism. Oxford; Clarendon
Press, 1994.
Wiredu, Kwasi. Philosophy and an African Culture.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980.
Endnotes
1. H.L.A. Hart, The
Concept of Law, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961). Pp. 204 – 205.
2. For more on this
debate, see the following works; H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law, ibid.; H.L.A.
Hart, “Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals”, Harvard Law Review,
vol. 71, no.4 (Feb. 1958). Pp.593 – 629; compare Lon L. Fuller’s rejoinder to
Hart, “Positivism and Fidelity to Law – A Reply to Professor Hart”, in the same
issue of Harvard Law Review, pp. 630 – 672; Joseph Raz, The Authority of Law, (
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979), especially chapter 3; Neil MacCormick, H.L.A.
Hart, (London, 1981); Neil MacCormick, “A Moralistic Case for a Moralistic
Law”, 20 Valparaiso Law Review (1986); Philip Soper, “Choosing a Legal Theory
on Moral Grounds”, Social Philosophy and Policy, (1987); Deryck Beyleveld and
Roger Brownsword, “ The Practical Differences Between Natural Law Theory and
Legal Positivism”, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, vol.5 (1985); pp. 1 – 32.
3. The African –
mostly Nigerian – writers under reference here include the following. F.U.
Okafor, “Legal Positivism and the African Legal Tradition”, International
Philosophical Quarterly, vol. Xxiv, no.2, issue 94 (June 1984); pp.157 – 164;
see also Okafor’s Igbo Philosophy of Law , (Enugu: Fourth Dimension Publishing
Co. Ltd., 1992), especially the closing remarks entitled “A Challenge to Legal
Positivism”; Rev. Dr. N.S.S. Iwe, “The Dangers of Legal Positivism to Our
Indigenous Values and Remedy”, in T.O. Elias, S.N. Awabara, and C.O. Akpamgbo
(eds.), African Indigenous Law (proceedings of workshop held between 7-9
August, 1974, at the University of Nigeria, Nsukka), published by the Institute
of African Studies, University of Nigeria, Nsukka; pp.232 – 250; Aguda Akinola,
The Judicial Process and the Third Republic, (Lagos: F&A Publishers Ltd.,
1992), especially chapter 5; see also Justice Aguda’s two-part opinion page
publications entitled “Back to Illegal ‘Laws’ 1”, in the Guardian newspaper of
Monday, May 16, 1994, and “Back to Illegal ‘Laws’ 2”, in the guardian newspaper
of Tuesday, may 17, 1994; Adetokunbo Okeaya-Inneh, “Why the Law Must Possess an
Inner Morality”, in the Guardian newspaper of Wednesday, August 4, 1993; A.O.
Obilade, “The Decline of Legal Positivism: A Critique of Two Tenets”, The
University of Ife Law Journal (1986), vol. 1&2, pp.94 – 111; J.M. Elegido,
Jurisprudence, (Ibadan: Spectrum Law Publishing, 1994), see especially the
authors introductory remarks on p. x.
4. In concrete
historical terms, instances of this mode of adoption of a legal theory by a
legal system are hard to find. It is conceivable that there was a period, in
the 1920s and 1930s, when the Realist “predictivist” theory of law could be
said to have been adopted in this sense, by the American legal system. This was
the period when influential realists occupied strategic positions in and out
the judiciary: from supreme court justices like Oliver Wendel Holmes jr., to
deans and professors at leading American law schools. In this regard, no one
can read Karl Llewelyn’s classic general introduction to law, The Bramble Bush
(first published in 1930), and not be struck by the pervasive commitment to the
predictivist conception of law. Llewelyn’s objective was to train lawyer - he was
professor of law at Columbia – who would be good forecasters of the future
course of judicial behaviour.
5. The concept of the
rule of recognition was introduced by H.L.A. Hart. See The Concept of Law,
chapter 6. The rule of recognition is the ultimate rule in a legal system, it
specifies the criteria for the identification (recognition) of every other rule
in the system. In other words, the rule of recognition contains the criteria of
legal validity in a legal system.
6. In this respect,
Professor Hart’s analysis of the positivist separability thesis, both in The
concept of Law , and in the Harvard Law Review article, cited above, is very
instructive. I say more on this later in the text.
7. Virtually, all the
Nigerian writers listed in note (3) above, make this claim.
8. Courses such as
Commercial law, Land law, Tort, Criminal law, Law of evidence, e.t.c., that
would make graduates of the law schools readily employable - by governments or
in private chambers – thus furnishing them with a secure source of livelihood,
enabling them, as Llewelyn used to put it, “to butter [their] bread, or to give
them bread to butter”.
9. A.V. Dicey was
quoted to have made this observation in an article in Law, Mag. & Rev.,
vol.5 . The quotation is from John C. Gray, “Some Definitions & Questions
in Jurisprudence”, Harvard Law Review, vol. Vi (1892/93), p.23. Happily,
neither Gray nor Dicey seems to endorse this “practising barrister’s” opinion
on jurisprudence.
10. Stromholm, Stig.
A Short History of Legal Thinking in the West, (Stockholm, Sweden: Norstedts
Forlag AB, 1985).
11. Austin, John.
The Province of Jurisprudence Determined, edited with an introduction by H.L.A.
Hart, (London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 3rd impression, 1968); lecture v, esp.
p135ff.
12. Ibid. p.145.
13. ibid. Austin
explains this at great length in lecture vi, pp.193 ff.
14. Ibid. pp. 13 –
14.
15. Ibid. p. 184.
16. A concise survey
of the realist movement is offered by Brian Leiter , in his article, “Legal
Realism”, in Dennis Patterson (ed.), A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal
Theory, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996); pp. 261 – 279.
17. Holmes, O. W.
(jnr.). “The Path of the Law”, Harvard Law Review, vol. 10 (1897); pp.457 –
478.
18. Hart, H.L.A. The
Concept of Law, op. Cit. Hart’s work has attracted a great deal of interest and
critical comments. For a sympathetic exposition of Hart’s philosophy of law,
see MacCormick, H.L.A. Hart, op.cit. Two collections of essays in honour of
Hart are particularly useful: Joseph Raz and P.M.S. Hacker (eds.), Law and
Morality: Essays in Honour of H.L.A. Hart, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977);
Ruth Gavison (ed.), Issues in Contemporary Legal Philosophy: The Influence of
H.L.A. Hart, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1987).
19. Kelsen, Hans.
The Pure Theory of Law, translated by Max Knight, (Berkeley & Los Angeles:
University of California Press, 1967). For a major collection of critical
essays on Kelsen’s work, see Stanley L. Paulson and Bonnie Litschewski Paulson
(eds.), Normativity and Norms:Critical Perspectives on Kelsenian Themes
(Oxford: ClarendonPress, 1998).
20. For more on
this, see my “Normative Positivism and Its Modern Critics”, in Legal Systems
& Legal Science; Proceedings of the 17th World Congress of the
International Association for Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy (IVR)
Bologna, June 16 – 21, 1995; ( ARSP – Beiheft 70: vol. Iv), edited by Marijan
Pavcnick and Gianfrancesco Zanetti. Pp. 49 – 57.
21. Hart, H.L.A. The
Concept of Law, op. Cit. P. 78.
22. Ibid. p. 95.
23. Ibid. pp. 181 –
182.
24. Hart, H.L.A.
“Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals”, Harvard Law Review, op. Cit.
P.
25. Greenawalt,
Kent. “Too Thin and Too Rich: Distinguishing Features of Legal Positivism”, in
Robert P. George (ed.), The Anatomy of Law: Essays on Legal Positivism,
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996). Pp. 1 – 29, at p.19. I added the emphasis.
26. Paulson, Stanley
L. “ Classical Legal Positivism at Nuremberg”, Philosophy and Public Affairs,
vol. 4, no. 2 (Winter, 1975); p.134.
27. ibid. p. 136.
28. A notable
exception is Elegido, Jurisprudence, op. Cit.
29. John Austin’s
classic, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined, was first published in 1832.
Austin’s widow, Sarah Austin published a second edition, with additional
materials on the uses of the study of Jurisprudence,, in 1861. Austin’s
statement of the positivist theory has since then been subjected to such
intense critical scrutiny and attack prompting a modern American commentator to
remark that Austin has been shot at so frequently for so long, that all that is
left of his theory are holes, no substance. The reception of classical legal
positivism has fluctuated from unreserved acclaim, to the most contemptuous
rejection. For example, John C. Gray records that Austin’s theory was
“considerably in vogue” from about 1861 (when the book was re- issued by Sarah
Austin) to about 1874. In 1874 “Sir Henry Maine dealt it a severe blow in his
last two lectures on the ‘Early History of Institutions’, since which time its
credit has been sensibly shaken” (John C. Gray, “Some Definitions and Questions
in Jurisprudence”, Harvard Law Review, vol. Vi (1892/93), p.22.). The profile
of Austinian positivism would thereafter rise and fall again . W.W. Buckland’s
observations seem to capture very aptly, the viscitude of the rising and
declining fortunes of classical legal positivism, especially Austin’s account
of it: “The analysis of legal concepts is what jurisprudence meant for the
students in the days of my youth. In fact it meant Austin. He was a religion;
today he seems to be regarded as a disease. “ (W.W. Buckland, Some Reflections
on Jurisprudence, (Cambridge, 1949), this passage was quoted by R.H.S. Tur,
“What is Jurisprudence?’, The Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 28, no iii (April
1978), p. 152). In what is generally regarded as the most comprehensive and
careful survey of Austin’s legal theory, professor Hart devoted the first three
chapters of his own classic, The Concept of Law, to a detailed critique of
Austin’s ideas. His verdict after the painstaking study seems to have put the
final nail on the coffin of reductivist positivism. The survey carried out in
the last three chapters is, in Hart’s words, “a record of failure.” P.78. Hart
is, nonetheless, persuaded that a more adequate account of the nature of law
can be constructed from the ruins of Austin’s theory.
30. Okafor,
“Positivism and the African Legal Tradition”, op.cit.p.157.
31. ibid.
32. ibid. p. 163.
33. Aguda, Akinola.
The Judicial Process and the Third Republic, op. Cit. P.81.
34. Iwe, N.S.S. “The
Dangers of Legal Positivism”, op. Cit.p.233.
35. ibid. p. 236.
36. Okafor, F.U. op.
Cit. P.
37. ibid. 161
38. ibid.
39. ibid.
40. ibid. 163.
41. Ibid. 162
42. ibid. 163.
43. Ibid.
44. ibid. 160.
45. Ibid.
46. ibid.
47. ibid. 162.
48. Ibid. 163.
49. Ibid. 159.
50. Taiwo, Olufemi.
“Legal Positivism and the African Legal Tradition: A Reply”, op. Cit. P. 200.
51. Ibid. 198.
52. Elias, T.O. The
Nature of African Customary Law, (Manchester: Manchester University Press,
1956); p. 287.
53. Ibid. 286.
54. It is
instructive that Bentham and his fellow utilitarians combined a strong
endorsement of the positivist doctrine with highly enlightened liberal
attitudes toward legal and other aspects of social reforms.
55. Bentham, Jeremy.
Theory of Legislation, edited by Ogden, p. 317; quoted on p.286 of Elias.
56. Ibid. The
emphasis is mine.
57. Elegido, J. M.
Jurisprudence, p. x.
58. Okafor, F. U.
“Legal Positivism and African Legal Tradition”, p. 164.
59. Taiwo, Olufemi.
“ Legal Positivism and African Legal Tradition: A Reply”, p.199.
60. Aguda, Akinola.
The Judicial Process and the Third Republic, pp. 82 – 83.
61. Ross, Alf. “
Validity and the Conflict Between Legal Positivism and Natural Law”, Revista
Juridica de Buenos Aires, (1961), vol. 4, p. 56.
62. Elegido, J.M.
see note (57) above.
63. Hart, H.L.A. The
Concept of Law, p. 78.
64. See my
“Normative Legal Positivism and Its Modern Critics”, note (20) above.
65. Ibid. p. 56.
66. Hart, H.L.A. “
Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals”, p. 618.
67. Taiwo. Olufemi.
“Legal Positivism and African Legal Tradition: A Reply”, p199.
68. Hart, H.L.A. “
Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals”, p.618.It is encouraging to
note that the kind of enquiries that Hart suggested are now been undertaken by
serious scholars. The findings thus far confirm what the defenders of the
positivist creed in legal theory have always insisted on. In an important
recent study , Paulson has shown , convincingly, that not only did legal
positivism not serve in any form to underwrite the atrocities committed by
officials and private individuals in Nazi Germany, but that the German
positivists were in fact among the most visible opponents of Nazism; an
ideological stance for which the legal positivists were routinely victimized
(Paulson, Stanley L. “Lon L. Fuller; Gustav Radbruch, and the ‘Positivist’
Theses”, Law and Philosophy, vol. 13, (1994). Pp. 313 – 359).
69. Soper, Philip.
“Choosing a Legal Theory on Moral Grounds”, 44, Social Philosophy and Policy,
vol. 4, issue 1, (1987); pp. 33 – 48.
70. Okafor, F. U. “
Legal Positivism and African Legal Tradition”, p. 164.
71. Nwakeze, P. C. “
A Critique of Olufemi Taiwo’s Criticism of Legal Positivism and African Legal
Tradition”, International Philosophical Quarterly, vol.xxvii, no.1, issue 105,
(March 1987); pp. 101 – 105.
Copyright 2001 Africa Resource Center, Inc.
Citation
Format
Oladosu,
Jare (2001). CHOOSING A LEGAL THEORY ON
CULTURAL GROUNDS: AN AFRICAN CASE FOR LEGAL POSITIVISM. West Africa Review: 2, 2 [iuicode: http://www.icaap.org/iuicode?101.2.2.2]
H.L.A.
Hart, "Legal Positivism"
from
Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals
71 HARV. L. REV. 593, 594-606 (1958
71 HARV. L. REV. 593, 594-606 (1958
SOURCED
FROM: http://www.kentlaw.edu/classes/rwarner/justice/syllabus/hpositiv.html
Editor's Note: H.L.A. Hart was Professor of
Jurisprudence in Oxford University from 1952 until 1968. He lectured and taught
on many occasions in the United States, and his writings in legal philosophy
have been extraordinarily influential.]
At the close of the eighteenth century and the
beginning of the nineteenth the most earnest thinkers in England about legal
and social problems and the architects of great reforms were the great
Utilitarians. Two of them, Bentham and Austin, constantly insisted on the need
to distinguish, firmly and with the maximum of clarity, law as it is from law
as it ought to be. This theme haunts their work, and they condemned the
natural-law thinkers precisely because they had blurred this apparently simple
but vital distinction. By contrast, at the present time in this country and to
a lesser extent in England, this separation between law and morals is held to
be superficial and wrong. Some critics have thought that it blinds men to the
true nature of law and its roots in social life.(4) Others have thought it not
only intellectually misleading but corrupting in practice, at its worst apt to
weaken resistance to state tyranny or absolutism,(5) and at [23]its best apt to
bring law into disrespect. The nonpejorative name "Legal Positivism,"
like most terms which are used as missiles in intellectual battles, has come to
stand for a baffling multitude of different sins. One of them is the sin, real
or alleged, of insisting, as Austin and Bentham did, on the separation of law
as it is and law as it ought to be.
How then has this reversal of the wheel come
about? What are the theoretical errors in this distinction? Have the practical
consequences of stressing the distinction as Bentham and Austin did been bad?
Should we now reject it or keep it? In considering these questions we should
recall the social philosophy which went along with the Utilitarians' insistence
on this distinction. They stood firmly but on their own utilitarian ground for
all the principles of liberalism in law and government. No one has ever
combined, with such even-minded sanity as the Utilitarians, the passion for
reform with respect for law together with a due recognition of the need to
control the abuse of power even when power is in the hands of reformers. One by
one in Bentham's works you can identify the elements of the Rechtstaat and all
the principles for the defense of which the terminology of natural law has in
our day been revived. Here are liberty of speech, and of press, the right of
association, the need that laws should be published and made widely known
before they are enforced, the need to control administrative agencies, the
insistence that there should be no criminal liability without fault, and the
importance of the principle of legality, nulla poena sine lege.(*) Some, I
know, find the political and moral insight of the Utilitarians a very simple
one, but we should not mistake this simplicity for superficiality nor forget
how favorably their simplicities compare with the profundities of other
thinkers. Take only one example: Bentham on slavery. He says the question at
issue is not whether those who are held as slaves can reason, but simply
whether they suffer.(11) Does this not compare well with the discussion of the
question in terms of whether or not there are some men whom Nature has fitted
only to be the living instruments of others? We owe it to Bentham more than
anyone else that we have stopped discussing this and similar questions of social
policy in that form.
So Bentham and Austin were not dry analysts fiddling with verbal
distinctions while cities burned, but were the vanguard of a movement which
laboured with passionate intensity and much success to bring about a better
society and better laws. Why then did they insist on the separation of law as
it is and law as it ought to be? What did they mean? Let us first see what they
said. Austin formulated the doctrine:The existence of law is one thing; its merit or demerit is another. Whether it be or be not is one enquiry; whether it be or be not conformable to an assumed standard, is a different enquiry. A law, which actually exists, is a law, though we happen to dislike it, or though it vary from the text, by which we regulate our approbation and disapprobation. This truth, when formally announced as an abstract proposition, is so simple and glaring that it seems idle to insist upon it. But simple and glaring as it is, when enunciated in abstract expressions, the enumeration of the instances in which it has been forgotten would fill a volume.
[24]
Sir William Blackstone, for example, says in his
"Commentaries," that the laws of God are superior in obligation to
all other laws; that no human laws should be suffered to contradict them; that
human laws are of no validity if contrary to them; and that all valid laws
derive their force from that Divine original.
Now, he may mean that all human laws ought to
conform to the Divine laws. If this be his meaning, I assent to it without
hesitation....Perhaps, again, he means that human lawgivers are themselves
obliged by the Divine laws to fashion the laws which they impose by that
ultimate standard, because if they do not, God will punish then. To this also I
entirely assent....
But the meaning of this passage of Blackstone, if it has a meaning, seems rather to be this: that no human law which conflicts with the Divine law is obligatory or binding; in other words, that no human law which conflicts with the Divine law is a law....(12)
Austin's protest against blurring the distinction between what law is and what it ought to be is quite general: it is a mistake, whatever our standard of what ought to be, whatever "the text by which we regulate our approbation or disapprobation." His examples, however, are always a confusion between law as it is and law as morality would require it to be. For him, it must be remembered, the fundamental principles of morality were God's commands, to which utility was an "index": besides this there was the actual accepted morality of a social group or "positive" morality.
But the meaning of this passage of Blackstone, if it has a meaning, seems rather to be this: that no human law which conflicts with the Divine law is obligatory or binding; in other words, that no human law which conflicts with the Divine law is a law....(12)
Austin's protest against blurring the distinction between what law is and what it ought to be is quite general: it is a mistake, whatever our standard of what ought to be, whatever "the text by which we regulate our approbation or disapprobation." His examples, however, are always a confusion between law as it is and law as morality would require it to be. For him, it must be remembered, the fundamental principles of morality were God's commands, to which utility was an "index": besides this there was the actual accepted morality of a social group or "positive" morality.
Bentham insisted on this distinction without
characterizing morality by reference to God but only, of course, by reference
to the principles of utility. Both thinkers' prime reason for this insistence
was to enable men to see steadily the precise issues posed by the existence of
morally bad laws, and to understand the specific character of the authority of
a legal order. Bentham's general recipe for life under the government of laws
was simple: it was "to obey punctually; to censure freely."(13) But
Bentham was especially aware, as an anxious spectator of the French revolution,
that this was not enough: the time might come in any society when the law's
commands were so evil that the question of resistance had to be faced, and it
was then essential that the issues at stake at this point should neither be
oversimplified nor obscured.(14) Yet, this was precisely what the confusion
between law and morals had done and Bentham found that the confusion had spread
symmetrically in two different directions. On the one hand Bentham had in mind
the anarchist who argues thus: "This ought not to be the law, therefore it
is not and I am free not merely to censure but to disregard it." On the
other hand he thought of the reactionary who argues: "This is the law,
therefore it is [25]what it ought to be," and thus stifles criticism at
its birth. Both errors, Bentham thought, were to be found in Blackstone: there
was his incautious statement that human laws were invalid if contrary to the
law of God,(15) and "that spirit of obsequious quietism that seems
constitutional in our Author" which "will scarce ever let him
recognise a difference" between what is and what ought to be.(16) This
indeed was for Bentham the occupational disease of lawyers: "[I]n the eyes
of lawyersnot to speak of their dupesthat is to say, as yet, the generality
of non-lawyersthe is and ought to be...were one and indivisible."(17)
There are therefore two dangers between which insistence on this distinction will
help us to steer: the danger that law and its authority may be dissolved in
man's conceptions of what law ought to be and the danger that the existing law
may supplant morality as a final test of conduct and so escape criticism.
In view of criticisms it is also important to distinguish several things
that the Utilitarians did not mean by insisting on their separation of law and
morals. They certainly accepted many of the things that might be called
"the intersection of law and morals." First, they never denied that,
as a matter of historical fact, the development of legal systems had been
powerfully influenced by moral opinion, and, conversely, that moral standards
had been profoundly influenced by law, so that the content of many legal rules
mirrored moral rules or principles. It is not in fact always easy to trace this
historical causal connection, but Bentham was certainly ready to admit its
existence; so too Austin spoke of the "frequent coincidence"(18) of
positive law and morality and attributed the confusion of what law is with what
law ought to be to this very fact.Secondly, neither Bentham nor his followers denied that by explicit legal provisions moral principles might at different points be brought into a legal system and form part of its rules, or that courts might be legally bound to decide in accordance with what they thought just or best. Bentham indeed recognized, as Austin did not, that even the supreme legislative power might be subjected to legal restraints by a constitution(19) and would not have denied that moral principles, like those of the fifth amendment, might form the content of such legal constitutional restraints. Austin differed in thinking that restraints on the supreme legislative power could not have the force of law, but would remain merely political or moral checks;(20) but of course he would have recognized that a statute, for example, might confer a delegated legislative power and restrict the area of its exercise by reference to moral principles.
[26]
What both Bentham and Austin were anxious to assert were the following two simple things: first, in the absence of an expressed constitutional or legal provision, it could not follow from the mere fact that a rule violated standards of morality that it was not a rule of law; and, conversely, it could not follow from the mere fact that a rule was morally desirable that it was a rule of law.
The history of this simple doctrine in the nineteenth century is too long and too intricate to trace here. Let me summarize it by saying that after it was propounded to the world by Austin it dominated English jurisprudence and constitutes part of the framework of most of those curiously English and perhaps unsatisfactory productionsthe omnibus surveys of the whole field of jurisprudence. A succession of these were published after a full text of Austin's lectures finally appeared in 1861. In each of them the utilitarian separation of law and morals is treated as something that enables lawyers to attain a new clarity. Austin was said by one of his English successors, Amos, "to have delivered the law from the dead body of morality that still clung to it";(21) and even Maine, who was critical of Austin at many points, did not question this part of his doctrine. In the United States men like N. St. John Green,(22) Gray, and Holmes considered that insistence on this distinction had enabled the understanding of law as a means of social control to get off to a fruitful new start; they welcomed it both as self-evident and as illuminatingas a revealing tautology. This distinction is, of course, one of the main themes of Holmes' most famous essay "The Path of the Law,"(23) but the place it had in the estimation of these American writers is best seen in what Gray wrote at the turn of the century in The Nature and Sources of the Law. He said:
The great gain in its fundamental conceptions which Jurisprudence made during the last century was the recognition of the truth that the Law of a State...is not an ideal, but something which actually exists....[I]t is not that which ought to be, but that which is. To fix this definitely in the Jurisprudence of the Common Law, is the feat that Austin accomplished.(24)
II.
So much for the doctrine in the heyday of its success. Let us turn now to some of the criticisms. * * *
There is, however, one major initial complexity by which criticism has been much confused. We must remember that the Utilitarians combined with their insistence on the separation of law and morals two other equally famous but dis-[27]tinct doctrines. One was the important truth that a purely analytical study of legal concepts, a study of the meaning of the distinctive vocabulary of the law, was as vital to our understanding of the nature of law as historical or sociological studies, though of course it could not supplant them. The other doctrine was the famous imperative theory of lawthat law is essentially a command.
These three doctrines constitute the utilitarian tradition in jurisprudence; yet they are distinct doctrines. It is possible to endorse the separation between law and morals and to value analytical inquiries into the meaning of legal concepts and yet think it wrong to conceive of law as essentially a command. One source of great confusion in the criticism of the separation of law and morals was the belief that the falsity of any one of these three doctrines in the utilitarian tradition showed the other two to be false; what was worse was the failure to see that there were three quite separate doctrines in this tradition. The indiscriminate use of the label "positivism" to designate ambiguously each of these three separate doctrines (together with some others which the Utilitarians never professed) has perhaps confused the issue more than any other single factor.(25) Some of the early American critics of the Austinian doctrine were, however, admirably clear on just this matter. Gray, for example, added at the end of the tribute to Austin, which I have already quoted, the words, "He may have been wrong in treating the Law of the State as being the command of the sovereign"(26) and he touched shrewdly on many points where the command theory is defective. But other critics have been less clearheaded and have thought that the inadequacies of the command theory which gradually came to light were sufficient to demonstrate the falsity of the separation of law and morals.
This was a mistake, but a natural one. To see how natural it was we must look a little more closely at the command idea. The famous theory that law is a command was a part of a wider and more ambitious claim. Austin said that the notion of a command was "the key to the sciences of jurisprudence and morals,"(27) and contemporary attempts to elucidate moral judgments in terms of [28]"imperative" or "prescriptive" utterances echo this ambitious claim. But the command theory, viewed as an effort to identify even the quintessence of law, let alone the quintessence of morals, seems breathtaking in its simplicity and quite inadequate. There is much, even in the simplest legal system, that is distorted if presented as a command. Yet the Utilitarians thought that the essence of a legal system could be conveyed if the notion of a command were supplemented by that of a habit of obedience. The simple scheme was this: What is a command? It is simply an expression by one person of the desire that another person should do or abstain from some action, accompanied by a threat of punishment which is likely to follow disobedience. Commands are laws if two conditions are satisfied: first, they must be general; second, they must be commanded by what (as both Bentham and Austin claimed) exists in every political society whatever its constitutional form, namely, a person or a group of persons who are in receipt of habitual obedience from most of the society but pay no such obedience to others. These persons are its sovereign. Thus law is the command of the uncommanded commanders of societythe creation of the legally untrammelled will of the sovereign who is by definition outside the law.
It is easy to see that this account of a legal system is threadbare. One can also see why it might seem that its inadequacy is due to the omission of some essential connection with morality. The situation which the simple trilogy of command, sanction, and sovereign avails to describe, if you take these notions at all precisely, is like that of a gunman saying to his victim, "Give me your money or your life." The only difference is that in the case of a legal system the gunman says it to a large number of people who are accustomed to the racket and habitually surrender to it. Law surely is not the gunman situation writ large, and legal order is surely not to be thus simply identified with compulsion.
This scheme, despite the points of obvious analogy between a statute and a command, omits some of the most characteristic elements of law. Let me cite a few. It is wrong to think of a legislature (and a fortiori an electorate) with a changing membership, as a group of persons habitually obeyed: this simple idea is suited only to a monarch sufficiently long-lived for a "habit" to grow up. Even if we waive this point, nothing which legislators do makes law unless they comply with fundamental accepted rules specifying the essential lawmaking procedures. This is true even in a system having a simple unitary constitution like the British. These fundamental accepted rules specifying what the legislature must do to legislate are not commands habitually obeyed, nor can they be expressed as habits of obedience to persons. They lie at the root of a legal system, and what is most missing in the utilitarian scheme is an analysis of what it is for a social group and its officials to accept such rules. This notion, not that of a command as Austin claimed, is the "key to the science of jurisprudence," or at least one of the keys.
Again, Austin, in the case of the democracy, looked past the legislators to the electorate as "the sovereign" (or in England as part of it). He thought that in the United States the mass of the electors to the state and federal legislatures were the sovereign whose commands, given by their "agent" in the legislatures, were law. But on this footing the whole notion of the sovereign outside the law being "habitually obeyed" by the "bulk" of the population must go: for in this case the "bulk" obeys the bulk, that is, it obeys itself. Plainly the general acceptance of the authority of a lawmaking procedure, irrespective of the changing individuals [29]who operate it from time to time, can be only distorted by an analysis in terms of mass habitual obedience to certain persons who are by definition outside the law, just as the cognate but much simpler phenomenon of the general social acceptance of a rule, say of taking off the hat when entering a church, would be distorted if represented as habitual obedience by the mass to specific persons.
Other critics dimly sensed a further and more important defect in the command theory, yet blurred the edge of an important criticism by assuming that the defect was due to the failure to insist upon some important connection between law and morals. This more radical defect is as follows. The picture that the command theory draws of life under law is essentially a simple relationship of the commander to the commanded, of superior to inferior, of top to bottom; the relationship is vertical between the commanders or authors of the law conceived of as essentially outside the law and those who are commanded and subject to the law. In this picture no place, or only an accidental or subordinate place, is afforded for a distinction between types of legal rules which are in fact radically different. Some laws require men to act in certain ways or to abstain from acting whether they wish to or not. The criminal law consists largely of rules of this sort: like commands they are simply "obeyed" or "disobeyed." But other legal rules are presented to society in quite different ways and have quite different functions. They provide facilities more or less elaborate for individuals to create structures of rights and duties for the conduct of life within the coercive framework of the law. Such are the rules enabling individuals to make contracts, wills, and trusts, and generally to mould their legal relations with others. Such rules, unlike the criminal law, are not factors designed to obstruct wishes and choices of an antisocial sort. On the contrary, these rules provide facilities for the realization of wishes and choices. They do not say (like commands) "do this whether you wish it or not," but rather "if you wish to do this, here is the way to do it." Under these rules we exercise powers, make claims, and assert rights. These phrases mark off characteristic features of laws that confer rights and powers; they are laws which are, so to speak, put at the disposition of individuals in a way in which the criminal law is not. Much ingenuity has gone into the task of "reducing" laws of this second sort to some complex variant of laws of the first sort. The effort to show that laws conferring rights are "really" only conditional stipulations of sanctions to be exacted from the person ultimately under a legal duty characterizes much of Kelsen's work.(28) Yet to urge this is really just to exhibit dogmatic determination to suppress one aspect of the legal system in order to maintain the theory that stipulation of a sanction, like Austin's command, represents the quintessence of law. One might as well urge that the rules of baseball were "really" only complex conditional directions to the scorer and that this showed their real or "essential" nature. * * *
* * * Rules that confer rights, though distinct from commands, need not be moral rules or coincide with them. Rights, after all, exist under the rules of cere-[30]monies, games, and in many other spheres regulated by rules which are irrelevant to the question of justice or what the law ought to be. Nor need rules which confer rights be just or morally good rules. The rights of a master over his slaves show us that. "Their merit or demerit," as Austin termed it, depends on how rights are distributed in society and over whom or what they are exercised. These critics indeed revealed the inadequacy of the simple notions of command and habit for the analysis of law; at many points it is apparent that the social acceptance of a rule or standard of authority (even if it is motivated only by fear or superstition or rests on inertia) must be brought into the analysis and cannot itself be reduced to the two simple terms. Yet nothing in this showed the utilitarian insistence on the distinction between the existence of law and its "merits" to be wrong.
Notes
1. Hart's critique of the command theory of Austin, and the related theory of Hans Kelsen, focuses on the functional character of a command and its relation to the notion of a sovereign, rather than on the coercive power of the state that, according to the earlier theorists, was a crucial part of what made such commands law and distinguished them from other non-law directives. Why might the earlier positivists have cared so much about defining law so as to emphasize its coercive character? Does the use of state coercion raise special moral considerations? Does defining the law in terms of state coercion serve to isolate those considerations? See Dale Nance, Legal Theory and the Pivotal Role of the Concept of Coercion, 57 U. COLO. L. REV. 1 (1985).
2. If one concedes that the law as it is may
diverge from law as it ought to be, then one needs terminology for referring to
each idea. When we say, "The law requires X," we are ordinarily
making a reference to the law "as it is." In these materials, we will
generally have this reference in mind when using the word "law"
without more. Yet it is frequently useful to refer to the other idea, the
"law as it ought to be." The ancient Greek philosopher Aristotle
seems to have used the term "justice" for this idea, meaning that
aspect of morality (or what Aristotle would call virtue) which ought to be
reflected in the law. Yet it is arguable that, all things considered, the law
should not always satisfy or enforce the demands of justice (Can you think of
examples?), so the identification seems imprecise. The eighteenth century
German philosopher Immanuel Kant seems to have used the term "right"
to refer to that part of morality which should be reflected in the law. But
similar problems arise, since one can imagine moral rights that ought not to be
made legal rights. (Again, can you think of examples?) In order to avoid
linguistic disputes, perhaps we should be content with a term like "ideal
law" to refer to the law as it ought to be, recognizing that what is ideal
may not be the same for all societies at all times; indeed, there may be no
unique ideal law for any given society at any given time. In subsequent Parts
of these materials, we will examine some of what can be said in characterizing
ideal law, at least in American society.
3. Professor Hart clearly distinguishes between utilitarianism and legal positivism, even though these views were both held by people like Austin and Bentham. Whereas positivism is a theory about the nature of law, that is a legal theory, utilitarianism is one form of moral theory. As Hart notes, utilitarian arguments can be used, and have been used, to criticize existing law, to indicate in what respects extant law differs from the ideal. But utilitarianism is not [31]the only such form of moral theory. In particular, it has been challenged as giving too little weight to the notion of individual rights.
To generalize, three types of moral argument can be identified. First, there are consequentialist (also called teleological) modes of argument, such as utilitarianism, in which moral duty is derived entirely from the goodness or badness of the consequences of action. Second, there are nonconsequentialist (also called deontological) modes, such as some arguments from "natural rights," in which moral duty is derived in some way that does not depend on the appraisal of the material consequences of accepting the argument, but rather on the inherent rightness or wrongness of the conduct in question. ("One ought to honor one's promise, even if that doesn't produce the best possible consequences.") Much modern philosophical debate has addressed the question of the priority of these two modes of moral thought. Especially prominent have been hypotheticals specifically designed to generate a conflict in the prescriptions that may be derived from utilitarian and rights-based approaches. They are usually some variation on the theme of what to do when you are faced with a situation in which intentionally killing an innocent person will result in the saving of many others. For example:
Suppose you are the driver of a trolley. The trolley rounds a bend, and there come into view ahead five track workmen, who have been repairing the track. The track goes through a bit of a valley at that point, and the sides are steep, so you must stop the trolley if you are to avoid running the five men down. You step on the brakes, but alas they don't work. Now you suddenly see a spur of track leading off to the right. You can turn the trolley onto it, and thus save the five men on the straight track ahead. Unfortunately,...there is one track workman on that spur of track. He can no more get off the track in time than the five can, so you will kill him if you turn the trolley onto him. Is it morally permissible [or required] for you to turn the trolley?
Judith Jarvis Thomson, The Trolley Problem, 94 YALE L.J. 1395 (1985).
Finally, there are what may be called "mixed" or "hybrid" modes of argument which try to combine the strengths of both consequentialist and nonconsequentialist analyses, allowing a place for each. For example, it has been suggested that the different modes of argument can be seen as different but complementary ways of checking and testing our moral intuitions against historically observed practices and conventions? See Randy Barnett, Foreword: Of Chickens and EggsThe Compatibility of Moral Rights and Consequentialist Analyses, 12 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 611 (1989).
Which mode of argument do you find most acceptable, the consequentialist, the nonconsequentialist, or a mixture? It is all too easy to opt for the mixed mode; bear in mind that many philosophers have found consequentialism and deontology to be fundamentally incompatible. You will have many occasions to think about these issues in the following materials.
4. What does it mean for a judge to accept positivism? How might a judge reason about his or her responsibilities in deciding a case if the judge accepts positivism? How does Justice Story's opinion in Prigg illustrate the issues? Did Story employ any moral theory in deciding the case? If so, was it utilitarian, or deontological, or mixed?
HANS
KELSEN
The Pure Theory of Law
SOURCED FROM: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/legal-positivism/
The idea
of a Pure Theory of Law was propounded by the formidable Austrian jurist and
philosopher Hans Kelsen (1881-1973). (See bibliographical note) Kelsen began
his long career as a legal theorist at the beginning of the 20th
century. The traditional legal philosophies at the time, were, Kelsen claimed,
hopelessly contaminated with political ideology and moralizing on the one hand,
or with attempts to reduce the law to natural or social sciences, on the other
hand. He found both of these reductionist endeavors seriously flawed. Instead,
Kelsen suggested a ‘pure’ theory of law which would avoid reductionism of any
kind. The jurisprudence Kelsen propounded “characterizes itself as a ‘pure’
theory of law because it aims at cognition focused on the law alone” and this
purity serves as its “basic methodological principle.” [PT1, 7] Note that this
anti-reductionism is both methodological and substantive. Kelsen firmly
believed that if the law is to be considered as a unique normative practice,
methodological reductionism should be avoided entirely. But this approach is
not only a matter of method. Reductionism should be avoided because the law is
a unique phenomenon, quite separate from morality and nature.
1. The Basic Norm
The
law, according to Kelsen, is a system of norms. Norms are ‘ought’ statements,
prescribing certain modes of conduct. Unlike moral norms, however, Kelsen
maintained that legal norms are created by acts of will. They are products of
deliberate human action. For instance, some people gather in a hall, speak,
raise their hands, count them, and promulgate a string of words. These are
actions and events taking place at a specific time and space. To say that what
we have described here is the enactment of a law, is to interpret
these actions and events by ascribing a normative significance to them. Kelsen,
however, firmly believed in Hume's distinction between ‘is’ and ‘ought’, and in
the impossibility of deriving ‘ought’ conclusions from factual premises alone.
Thus Kelsen believed that the law, which is comprised of norms or ‘ought’
statements, cannot be reduced to those natural actions and events which give
rise to it. The gathering, speaking and raising of hands, in itself, is not the
law; legal norms are essentially ‘ought’ statements, and as such, they cannot
be deduced from factual premises alone.
How is
it possible, then, to ascribe an ‘ought’ to those actions and events which
purport to create legal norms? Kelsen's reply is enchantingly simple: we
ascribe a legal ought to such norm-creating acts by, ultimately, presupposing
it. Since ‘ought’ cannot be derived from ‘is’, and since legal norms are
essentially ‘ought’ statements, there must be some kind of an ‘ought’
presupposition at the background, rendering the normativity of law
intelligible.
As opposed
to moral norms which, according to Kelsen, are typically deduced from other
moral norms by syllogism (e.g., from general principles to more particular
ones), legal norms are always created by acts of will. Such an act can only
create law, however, if it is in accord with another ‘higher’ legal norm that
authorizes its creation in that way. And the ‘higher’ legal norm, in turn, is
valid only if it has been created in accordance with yet another, even ‘higher’
legal norm that authorizes its enactment. Ultimately, Kelsen argued, one must
reach a point where the authorizing norm is no longer the product of an act of
will, but is simply presupposed, and this is, what Kelsen called, the Basic
Norm. More concretely, Kelsen maintained that in tracing back such a ‘chain of
validity’ (to use Raz's terminology), one would reach a point where a ‘first’
historical constitution is the basic authorizing norm of the rest of the legal
system, and the Basic Norm is the presupposition of the validity of that first
constitution.
Kelsen
attributed two main explanatory functions to the Basic Norm: it explains both
the unity of a legal system and the reasons for the legal validity of norms.
[PT2, 193] Apparently, Kelsen believed that these two ideas are very closely
related, since he seems to have maintained that the legal validity of a norm
and its membership in a given legal system are basically the same thing.
Furthermore, Kelsen argued that every two norms which derive their validity
from a single Basic Norm necessarily belong to the same legal system and, vice
versa, so that all legal norms of a given legal system derive their
validity from one Basic Norm. It is widely acknowledged that Kelsen erred in
these assumptions about the unity of legal systems. Generally speaking, in
spite of the considerable interest in Kelsen's theory of legal systems and
their unity that derives from a single Basic Norm, critics have shown that this
aspect of Kelsen's theory is refutable. Although it is certainly true that the
law always comes in systems, the unity of the system and its separation from
other systems is almost never as neat as Kelsen assumed. [see Raz, ‘Kelsen's
Theory of the Basic Norm’.]
However,
the role of the Basic Norm in explaining the normativity of law is crucially
important. The presupposition of the Basic Norm as the condition of validity of
legal norms marks Kelsen's theory as ‘pure’, and distinguishes it from other
theories in the Legal Positivist tradition. Contemporary legal positivists have
traditionally accounted for the normativity of law in terms of social facts:
people tend to perceive of the legal norms in their community as valid because,
ultimately, there are certain social conventions, or Rules of Recognition in
H.L.A. Hart's terminology, that determine who is authorized to make law and how
law making is to be done. But this is precisely the kind of reductionism that
the Pure Theory strives to deny. Kelsen was convinced that any attempt to
ground the law's normativity, namely, its ‘ought’ aspect, is doomed to failure
if it is only based on facts, whether those facts are natural or social. Once
again, to account for an ‘ought’ conclusion, one needs some ‘ought’ in the
premises. Therefore, Kelsen thought, the normativity of law, as a genuine
‘ought’, must, ultimately, be presupposed.
Common
wisdom has it that in this kind of reasoning Kelsen self-consciously employs a
Kantian Transcendental argument to establish the necessary presupposition of
the Basic Norm. Thus the argument takes the following form:
- P.
- P is possible only if Q.
- Therefore, Q.
In
Kelsen's case, P stands for the fact that legal norms are ‘ought’
statements, and Q is the presupposition of the Basic Norm. [PT2, 202].
Furthermore, commentators have pointed out that just as Kant's epistemology is
an attempt to find the middle way between dogmatic Rationalism and skeptical
Empiricism, Kelsen's pure theory of law is an attempt to find a middle way
between Natural Law's dogmatism, and Positivism's reduction of law to the
social sciences. [See Paulson, Introduction] But it is worth keeping in mind
that Kelsen's argument about the Basic Norm is an explicitly shallow
form of Kantian epistemology. The Kantian categories and modes of perception
are not optional; they form a deep, universal, and necessary feature of
rational cognition. One should recall that it is Humean skepticism
that Kant strove to answer. Kelsen, however, remains Humean through and
through, Kantian influences notwithstanding. First, Kelsen was very skeptical
about any objectivist moral theory, Kant's included. [PT1, 16; PT2, 63-65]
Second, Kelsen does not claim that the presupposition of the Basic Norm is a
necessary feature, or category, of rational cognition. The Basic Norm is an
‘ought’ presumption and, as such, optional. It is not necessary for anyone to
accept the Basic Norm. The Basic Norm is necessarily presupposed only by those
who accept the ‘ought’, namely, the normativity, of the law. Likewise, those
who believe in the normativity of a religious order must presuppose a Basic
Norm that ‘one ought to obey God's commands’. But in both cases, there is
nothing in the nature of things which would compel any particular person to
adopt such a normative perspective. Kelsen's argument does not rule out atheism
or anarchism. However, even the anarchist, Kelsen maintained, must presuppose
the Basic Norm if she is to account for the normativity of law. But again, this
presupposition is only an intellectual tool, not a normative commitment, and as
the latter, it is entirely optional.
2. The Normativity of Law
This
analogy between law and religion, on which Kelsen often dwells, is more limited
than it first appears, however. The normativity of religion, like that of
morality, does not depend on the actual obedience of their respective subjects.
For those, for example, who presuppose the basic norm of Christianity, the
latter would be valid even if there are no other Christians around. But this,
as Kelsen explicitly admits, is not the case with law. The validity of a legal
system partly, but crucially, depends on its actual practice: “A legal order is
regarded as valid, if its norms are by and large effective (that is,
actually applied and obeyed).” [PT2, 212] Furthermore, the actual content of
the Basic Norm depends on its ‘effectiveness’. As Kelsen repeatedly argued, a
successful revolution brings about a radical change in the content of the Basic
Norm. Suppose, for example, that in a given legal system the Basic Norm is that
the constitution enacted by Rex One is binding. At a certain point, a coup
d'etat takes place and a republican government is successfully installed.
At this point, Kelsen admits, “one presupposes a new basic norm, no longer the
basic norm delegating law making authority to the monarch, but a basic norm
delegating authority to the revolutionary government.” [PT1, 59].
This
is very problematic, however, since it raises the suspicion that Kelsen has
violated his own categorical injunction against deriving ‘ought’ from ‘is’.
Kelsen was not unaware of the difficulty. In the first edition of the Pure
Theory of Law, he suggests the solution to this problem by introducing
international law as the source of validity for changes in the basic norms of
municipal legal systems. It follows from the basic norm of international law,
Kelsen maintains, that state sovereignty is determined by successful control
over a given territory. Therefore, the changes in the basic norm which stem
from successful revolutions can be accounted for in legalistic terms, relying
on the dogmas of international law. [PT1, 61-62] The price Kelsen had to pay
for this solution, however, is rather high: he was compelled to claim that all
municipal legal systems derive their validity from international law, and this
entails that there is only one Basic Norm in the entire world, namely, the
Basic Norm of public international law. Although this solution is repeated in
the second edition of the Pure Theory of Law [214-215], Kelsen presented it
there with much more hesitation, perhaps just as an option which would make
sense. It is not quite clear whether Kelsen really adhered to it. The
hesitation is understandable; after all, the idea that municipal legal systems
derive their legal validity from international law would strike most jurists
and legal historians as rather fanciful and anachronistic. (We should recall
that the development of international law is a relatively recent phenomenon in
the history of law.)
So we
are back to the question of how ‘pure’ Kelsen's theory really is, if it is
conceded that the content of the Basic Norm is basically determined by social
practice. The answer depends on how we construe the explanatory function of the
Basic Norm: Neither Kelsen nor his critics seem to have been careful to
distinguish between the role of the Basic Norm in answering the question of how
we identify the law as such, and in answering the question of law's normativity.
An answer to the question of what counts as law or as law creating acts in a
given community cannot be detached from practice, namely, social conventions.
The social conventions prevalent in any given community determine, ultimately,
what counts as law in that community. (See the Nature of Law) On the other
hand, Kelsen is right to insist that social conventions, by themselves, could
not explain the ‘ought’ which is inherent in law as a normative system. Such an
‘ought’ cannot be constituted by the conventions. Social conventions can only
determine what the practice is, and how one would go about in engaging in it;
conventions cannot determine that one ought to engage in the practice. [see
Marmor, Positive Law & Objective Values, 25-33] Consider, for
example, the analogy of a structured game, like chess. What chess is, and how
one should play the game, are determined by its constitutive rules or
conventions. Those rules which constitute the game of chess, however, cannot
provide anyone with a complete reason to play the game. The normativity of the
game is conditional; it depends on a prior reason, or commitment, to play the
game. We cannot say, for example, that one “ought to move the bishop
diagonally” unless we assume that the agent wants to play chess. The fact that
the rules of chess require the players to move the bishop diagonally is not, in
itself, a reason for doing so, unless, again, it is assumed that it is chess
that one wants to play. Now, it is precisely this kind of assumption that the
Basic Norm is there to capture. Just as the normativity of chess could not be
explained without presupposing, as it were, that the players want to engage in
that particular game, so the normativity of law must be premised on the Basic
Norm.
Thus,
it would seem that Kelsen's anti-reductionism is only partly successful. The
explanatory role of the Basic Norm must be confined to the normativity of law.
But in order to explain what counts as law and how law is identified and
distinguished from other normative practices, the Basic Norms is not
sufficient; one must refer to the social conventions which prevail in the
relevant community.
None
of this means, however, that Kelsen's account of the normativity of law is
unproblematic. There are two main problems that may be worth exploring. First,
Kelsen has never made it quite clear whether he maintains that the ‘ought’
which is presupposed in the legal domain is the same kind of ‘ought’ which
would be characteristic of morality or, indeed, any other normative domain.
Kelsen seems to have faced a dilemma here which would not be easy to resolve.
On the one hand, he wanted to avoid the mistake which he attributed to the
Natural Law tradition of reducing the normativity of law to moral ‘ought’.
Kelsen has repeatedly argued that Natural Law, which would reduce the legal
‘ought’ to moral ‘ought’ fails because it can only achieve an account of the
normativity of law at the expense of missing its target: If the only notion of
validity is a moral one, we are left with no room for the concept of legal
validity. Natural Law, as Kelsen understood it, does not make any allowance for
the possibility that a norm is legally valid but morally wrong. Would this
imply, then, that the kind of ‘ought’ which is presupposed by the Basic Norm is
somehow different from moral ‘ought’? And what would the difference consist in?
One should bear in mind that Kelsen thought that the normativity of morality,
like that of religion or any other normative domain, is also ‘presupposed’. So
here is the dilemma: either Kelsen maintains that the legal ‘ought’ and moral
‘ought’ are two different kinds of ‘ought’ (which, I think, is the stance he
adopted in his earlier writings), but then it would be very difficult to
explain what the difference consists in, given that both kinds of ‘ought’ are
simply presupposed; or else, Kelsen would have to maintain that the moral and
legal ‘ought’ are basically the same, in which case, he would be hard pressed
to explain how he avoids the same kind of mistake which he attributed to the
Natural Law tradition.
Secondly,
and perhaps this is part of the reason for the former confusion, Kelsen's
account of the normativity of law is seriously impeded by his Humean skepticism
about the objectivity of morality, justice, or any other evaluative scheme. The
view one gets, especially from Kelsen's later writings, is that there are
countless potential normative systems, like morality, law, religion, etc., that
one can either accept or not just by presupposing their respective Basic Norms.
But without any rational or objective grounding of such evaluative systems, the
choice of any Basic Norm remains rather whimsical, devoid of any reason. It is
difficult to understand how normativity can really be explained on the
basis of such rationally groundless choices.
Bibliography
Note
Kelsen's
academic publications span over almost seven decades in which he published
dozens of books and hundreds of articles. Only about a third of this vast
literature has been translated to English. Kelsen's two most important books on
the pure theory of law are the first edition of his Reine Rechtslehre,
published in 1934, and recently translated to English under the title Introduction
to the Problems of Legal Theory, (Paulson and Paulson trans.) Oxford 2002,
and the second edition which Kelsen published in 1960, Pure Theory of Law,
(Knight trans.), UC Berkeley press, 1967. The second edition is a considerably
extended version of the first edition. These books are abbreviated in the test
as PT1 and PT2 respectively. In addition, most of the themes in these two books
also appear in Kelsen's General Theory of Law and State, (1945),
(Wedberg trans.), Russell & Russell, NY 1961 and What is Justice?,
UC Berkeley Press, 1957. Other relevant publications in English include ‘The
Pure Theory of Law and Analytical Jurisprudence’, 55 Harvard L. Rev.
(1941), 44, ‘Professor Stone and the Pure Theory of Law: A Reply’, (1965), 17
Stanford L. Rev. 1128, and ‘On the Pure Theory of Law’ (1966), 1
Israel L. Rev. 1.
For a
complete list of Kelsen's publications which have appeared in English see the
Appendix to H. Kelsen, General Theory of Norms (M. Hartney trans.)
Oxford, 1991, pp. 440-454.
Other Sources
- Harris, J.W., Legal Philosophies, Butterworths, 1980, chapter 6.
- Hart, H.L.A., The Concept of Law, Oxford 1961, chapter 3.
- -----, ‘Kelsen's Doctrine of the Unity of Law’, in H.E. Kiefer and M.K. Munitz (eds), Ethics and Social Justice, NY, 1970.
- Marmor, A., Objective Law and Positive Values, Oxford 2001, chapter 2.
- Paulson, S., Introduction to Kelsen's Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory, Clarendon 2002, xvii.
- Raz, J., The Concept of a Legal System, (2nd ed.) Oxford 1980.
- -----, ‘Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm’ in Raz, The Authority of Law, Oxford 1979, 122.
JOHN AUSTIN
SOURCED FORM: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/austin-john/
John
Austin is considered by many to be the creator of the school of analytical
jurisprudence, as well as, more specifically, the approach to law known as
"legal positivism." Austin's particular command theory of law has
been subject to pervasive criticism, but its simplicity gives it an evocative
power that cannot be ignored.
1. Life
John Austin's life (1790-1859) was filled with disappointment and
unfulfilled expectations. His influential friends (who included Jeremy Bentham,
James Mill, John Stuart Mill and Thomas Carlyle) were impressed by his
intellect and his conversation, and predicted he would go far. However, in
public dealings, Austin's nervous disposition, shaky health, tendency towards
melancholy, and perfectionism combined to end quickly careers at the Bar, in
academia, and in government service. (Hamburger 1985, 1992)
Austin
was born to a Suffolk merchant family, and served briefly in the military
before beginning his legal training. He was called to the Bar in 1818, but he
took on few cases, and quit the practice of law in 1825. Austin shortly
thereafter obtained an appointment to the first Chair of Jurisprudence at the
recently established University College London. He prepared for his lectures by
study in Bonn, and evidence of the influence of continental legal and political
ideas can be found scattered throughout Austin's writings.
Lectures
from the course he gave were eventually published in 1832 as "Province of
Jurisprudence Determined." (Austin 1995) However, attendance at his
courses was small and getting smaller, and he gave his last lecture in 1833. A
short-lived effort to give a similar course of lectures at the Inner Temple met
the same result. Austin resigned his University College London Chair in 1835.
He later briefly served on the Criminal Law Commission, and as a Royal
Commissioner to Malta, but he never found either success or contentment. He did
some occasional writing on political themes, but his plans for longer works
never came to anything during his lifetime, due apparently to some combination
of perfectionism, melancholy, and writer's block. His changing views on moral,
political, and legal matters also apparently hindered both the publication of a
revised edition of "Province of Jurisprudence Determined," and the
completion of a longer project started when his views had been different.
Much
of whatever success Austin found during his life, and after, must be attributed
to his wife Sarah, for her tireless support, both moral and economic (during
the later years of their marriage, they lived primarily off her efforts as a
translator and reviewer), and her work to publicize his writings after his
death (including the publication of a more complete set of his Lectures on
Jurisprudence) (Austin 1873).
While
Austin's work was influential in the decades after his death, its impact seemed
to subside substantially by the beginning of the twentieth century. A
significant portion of Austin's current reputation derives from H.L.A. Hart's
use (1958, 1994) of Austin's theory as a foil for the explanation of Hart's
own, more nuanced approach to legal theory. In recent decades some theorists
have revisited Austin's work, offering new characterizations and defenses of
his ideas (e.g., Morison 1982, Rumble 1985).
2. Analytical Jurisprudence and Legal Positivism
Early in his career, Austin came under the influence of Jeremy Bentham, and
Bentham's utilitarianism is evident (though with some differences) in the work
for which Austin is best known today. On Austin's reading of utilitarianism,
Divine will is equated with Utilitarian principles: "utility is the index
to the law of God ... . To make a promise which general utility condemns, is an
offense against the law of God" (Austin 1873: Lecture VI, p. 307; see also
Austin 1995: Lecture II, p. 41). This particular reading of utilitarianism,
however, has had little long-term influence, though it seems to have been the
part of his work that received the most attention in his own day (Rumble 1995:
p. xx). Austin early on shared many of the ideas of the Benthamite
philosophical radicals; he was "a strong proponent of modern political
economy, a believer in Hartleian metaphysics, and a most enthusiastic
Malthusian." (Rumble 1985: pp. 16-17)
Austin's
importance to legal theory lies elsewhere -- his theorizing about law was novel
at three different levels of generality. First, he was arguably the first
writer to approach the theory of law analytically (as contrasted with
approaches to law more grounded in history or sociology, or arguments about law
which were secondary to more general moral and political theories). Analytical
jurisprudence emphasizes the analysis of key concepts, including "law,"
"(legal) right," "(legal) duty," and "legal
validity." Though analytical jurisprudence has been challenged by some in
recent years (e.g., Leiter 1998), it remains the dominant approach to
discussing the nature of law. Analytical jurisprudence, an approach to
theorizing about law, has sometimes been confused with what the American legal
realists (an influential group of theorists prominent in the early decades of
the 20th century) called "legal formalism" -- a narrow approach to
how judges should decide cases. The American legal realists saw Austin in
particular, and analytical jurisprudence in general, as their opponents in
their critical and reform-minded efforts. In this, the realists were simply
mistaken; unfortunately, it is a mistake that can still be found in some
contemporary legal commentators.
(There
is some evidence that Austin's views later in his life may have moved away from
analytical jurisprudence towards something more approximating the historical
jurisprudence school. (Hamburger 1985: pp. 178-91))
Second,
within analytical jurisprudence, Austin was the first systematic exponent of a
view of law known as "legal positivism." Most of the important
theoretical work on law prior to Austin had treated jurisprudence as though it
were merely a branch of moral theory or political theory: asking how should the
state govern? (and when were governments legitimate?), and under what
circumstances did citizens have an obligation to obey the law? Austin
specifically, and legal positivism generally, offered a quite different
approach to law: as an object of "scientific" study, dominated
neither by prescription nor by moral evaluation. Subtle jurisprudential
questions aside, Austin's efforts to treat law systematically gained popularity
in the late 19th century among English lawyers who wanted to approach their
profession, and their professional training, in a more serious and rigorous
manner (Cotterrell 1989: pp. 79-81).
Legal
positivism asserts (or assumes) that it is both possible and valuable to have a
morally neutral descriptive (or "conceptual" -- though this is not a
term Austin used) theory of law. (The main competitor to legal positivism, in
Austin's day as in our own, has been natural law theory.) Legal positivism does
not deny that moral and political criticism of legal systems are important, but
insists that a descriptive or conceptual approach to law is valuable, both on
its own terms and as a necessary prelude to criticism.
There
were theorists prior to Austin who arguably offered views similar to legal
positivism or who at least foreshadowed legal positivism in some way. Among
these would be Thomas Hobbes, with his amoral view of laws as the product of
Leviathan (Hobbes 1996); David Hume, with his argument for separating
"is" and "ought" (which worked as a sharp criticism for
some forms of natural law theory, which purported to derive moral truths from
statements about human nature) (Hume 2000); and Jeremy Bentham, with his
attacks on judicial lawmaking and on those, like Sir William Blackstone, who justified
such lawmaking with natural-law-like justifications (Bentham 1970, 1996).
Austin's
famous formulation of what could be called the "dogma" of legal
positivism is as follows:
The existence of law is one thing; its merit or demerit is another. Whether
it be or be not is one enquiry; whether it be or be not conformable to an
assumed standard, is a different enquiry. A law, which actually exists, is a
law, though we happen to dislike it, or though it vary from the text, by which
we regulate our approbation and disapprobation. (Austin 1995: Lecture V, p.
157)
Third, Austin's version of legal positivism, a "command theory of
law" (which will be detailed in the next section) has also been
influential. Austin's theory had similarities with the views developed by
Jeremy Bentham, whose theory could also be characterized as a "command
theory." However, Austen's work was more influential in this area, because
Bentham's jurisprudential writings did not appear in an even-roughly systematic
form until well after Austin's work had already been published. (Bentham 1970,
1996; Cotterrell 1989: pp. 52-53)
3. Austin's Views
Austin's basic approach was to ascertain what can be said generally, but
still with interest, about all laws. Austin's analysis can be seen as either a
paradigm of, or a caricature of, analytical philosophy, in that his discussions
are dryly full of distinctions, but are thin in argument. The modern reader is
forced to fill in much of the meta-theoretical, justificatory work, as it
cannot be found in the text. Where Austin does articulate his methodology and
objective, it is a fairly traditional one: he "endeavored to resolve a law
(taken with the largest signification which can be given to that term properly)
into the necessary and essential elements of which it is composed."
(Austin 1995: Lecture V, p. 117)
As to
what is the core nature of law, Austin's answer is that laws ("properly so
called") are commands of a sovereign. He clarifies the concept of positive
law (that is, man-made law) by analyzing the constituent concepts of his
definition, and by distinguishing law from other concepts that are similar:
- "Commands" involve an expressed wish that something be done, and "an evil" to be imposed if that wish is not complied with.
- Rules are general commands (applying generally to a class), as contrasted with specific or individual commands ("drink wine today" or "John Major must drink wine").
- Positive law consisted of those commands laid down by a sovereign (or its agents), to be contrasted to other law- givers, like God's general commands, and the general commands of an employer.
- The "sovereign" was defined as a person (or collection of persons) who receives habitual obedience from the bulk of the population, but who does not habitually obey any other (earthly) person or institution. Austin thought that all independent political societies, by their nature, have a sovereign.
- Positive law should also be contrasted with
"laws by a close analogy" (which includes positive morality,
laws of honor, international law, customary law, and constitutional law)
and "laws by remote analogy" (e.g., the laws of physics).
(Austin 1995: Lecture I).
Austin
also wanted to include within "the province of jurisprudence" certain
"exceptions," items which did not fit his criteria but should
nonetheless be studied with other "laws properly so called":
repealing laws, declarative laws, and "imperfect laws" - laws
prescribing action but without sanctions (a concept Austin ascribes to
"Roman [law] jurists"). (Austin 1995: Lecture I, p. 36)
In the
criteria set out above, Austin succeeded in delimiting law and legal rules from
religion, morality, convention, and custom. However, also excluded from
"the province of jurisprudence" were customary law (except to the
extent that the sovereign had, directly or indirectly, adopted such customs as
law), public international law, and parts of constitutional law. (These
exclusions alone would make Austin's theory problematic for most modern
readers.)
Within
Austin's approach, whether something is or is not "law" depends on
which people have done what: the question turns on an empirical investigation,
and it is a matter mostly of power, not of morality. Of course, Austin is not
arguing that law should not be moral, nor is he implying that it rarely is.
Austin is not playing the nihilist or the skeptic. He is merely pointing out
that there is much that is law that is not moral, and what makes something law
does nothing to guarantee its moral value. "The most pernicious laws, and
therefore those which are most opposed to the will of God, have been and are
continually enforced as laws by judicial tribunals." (Austin 1995: Lecture
V, p. 158).
In
contrast to his mentor Bentham, Austin had no objection to judicial lawmaking,
which Austin called "highly beneficial and even absolutely
necessary." (Austin, 1995: Lecture V, p. 163) Nor did Austin find any
difficulty incorporating judicial lawmaking into his command theory: he
characterized that form of lawmaking, along with the occasional legal/judicial
recognition of customs by judges, as the "tacit commands" of the
sovereign, the sovereign's affirming the "orders" by its
acquiescence. (Austin 1995: Lecture 1, pp. 35-36).
4. Criticisms
As many readers come to Austin's theory mostly through its criticism by other
writers (prominently, that of H.L.A. Hart), the weaknesses of the theory are
almost better known than the theory itself:
- In many societies, it is hard to identify a "sovereign" in Austin's sense of the word (a difficulty Austin himself experienced, when he was forced to describe the British "sovereign" awkwardly as the combination of the King, the House of Lords, and all the electors of the House of Commons). Additionally, a focus on a "sovereign" makes it difficult to explain the continuity of legal systems: a new ruler will not come in with the kind of "habit of obedience" that Austen sets as a criterion for a system's rule-maker. However, one could argue (see Harris 1977) that the sovereign is best understood as a constructive metaphor: that law should be viewed as if it reflected the view of a single will (a similar view, that law should be interpreted as if it derived from a single will, can be found in Ronald Dworkin's work (1986)).
- A "command" model seems to fit some aspects of law poorly (e.g., rules which grant powers to officials and to private citizens - of the latter, the rules for making wills, trusts, and contracts are examples), while excluding other matters (e.g., international law) which we are not inclined to exclude in the category "law."
- More generally, it seems more distorting than enlightening to reduce all law to one type. For example, rules that empower people to make wills and contracts perhaps can be re-characterized as part of a long chain of reasoning for eventually imposing a sanction (Austin spoke in this context of the sanction of "nullity") on those who fail to comply with the relevant provisions. However, such a re-characterization this misses the basic purpose of those sorts of laws - they are arguably about granting power and autonomy, not punishing wrongdoing.
- A theory which portrays law solely in terms of power fails to distinguish rules of terror from forms of governance sufficiently just that they are accepted as legitimate by their own citizens.
(Austin
was aware of some of these lines of attack, and had responses ready; it is
another matter whether his responses were adequate.) It should also be noted
that Austin's work shows a silence on questions of methodology, though this may
be forgivable, given the early stage of jurisprudence. As discussed in an
earlier section, in many ways, Austin was blazing a new path.
When
H.L.A. Hart revived legal positivism in the middle of the 20th
century (Hart 1958, 1994), he did it by criticizing and building on Austin's
theory: for example, Hart's theory did not try to reduce all laws to one kind
of rule, but emphasized the varying types and functions of legal rules; and
Hart's theory, grounded partly on the distinction between
"obligation" and "being obliged," was built around the fact
that some participants within legal systems "accepted" the legal
rules as reasons for action, above and beyond the fear of sanctions.
5. A Revisionist View?
Some modern commentators appreciate in Austin elements that were probably
not foremost in his mind (or that of his contemporary readers). For example,
one occasionally sees Austin portrayed as the first "realist": in
contrast both to the theorists that came before Austin and to some modern
writers on law, Austin is seen as having a keener sense of the connection of
law and power, and the importance of keeping that connection at the forefront
of analysis. (cf. Cotterrell 1989: pp. 57-79) When circumstances seem to
warrant a more critical, skeptical or cynical approach to law and government,
Austin's equation of law and force will be attractive - however distant such a
reading may be from Austin's own liberal-utilitarian views at the time of his
writing, and his even more conservative political views later in his life.
(Hamburger, 1985)
Bibliography
Primary Sources
- Austin, John, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined, W. Rumble (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995) (first published, 1832)
- -----, Lectures on Jurisprudence, or The Philosophy of Positive Law, two vols., R. Campbell (ed.), 4th edition, London: John Murray, 1873
Natural
Law
SOURCED ON
11TH AUGUST 2004 BY JOSIAH M.N. FROM
The term 'natural law' is ambiguous. It refers to
a type of moral theory, as well as to a type of legal theory, despite the fact
that the core claims of the two kinds of theory are logically independent.
According to natural law ethical theory, the moral standards that govern human
behavior are, in some sense, objectively derived from the nature of human
beings. According to natural law legal theory, the authority of at least some
legal standards necessarily derives, at least in part, from considerations
having to do with the moral merit of those standards. There are a number of
different kinds of natural law theories of law, differing from each other with
respect to the role that morality plays in determining the authority of legal
norms.
I. Two Kinds of Natural Law Theory
At the outset, it is important to distinguish two
kinds of theory that go by the name of natural law. The first is a theory of
morality that is roughly characterized by the following theses. First, moral
propositions have what is sometimes called objective standing in the sense that
such propositions are the bearers of objective truth-value; that is, moral
propositions can be objectively true or false. Though moral objectivism is
sometimes equated with moral realism (see, e.g., Moore 1992, 190: "the
truth of any moral proposition lies in its correspondence with a mind- and
convention-independent moral reality"), the relationship between the two
theories is controversial. Geoffrey Sayre-McCord (1988), for example, views
moral objectivism as one species of moral realism, but not the only form; on
Sayre-McCord's view, moral subjectivism and moral intersubjectivism are also
forms of moral realism. Strictly speaking, then, natural law moral theory is
committed only to the objectivity of moral norms.
The second thesis constituting the core of
natural law moral theory is the claim that standards of morality are in some
sense derived from, or entailed by, the nature of the world and the nature of
human beings. St. Thomas Aquinas, for example, identifies the rational nature
of human beings as that which defines moral law: "the rule and measure of
human acts is the reason, which is the first principle of human acts"
(Aquinas, ST I-II, Q.90, A.I). On this common view, since human beings are by
nature rational beings, it is morally appropriate that they should behave in a
way that conforms to their rational nature. Thus, Aquinas derives the moral law
from the nature of human beings (thus, "natural law").
But there is another kind of natural law theory
having to do with the relationship of morality to law. According to natural law
theory of law, there is no clean division between the notion of law and the
notion of morality. Though there are different versions of natural law theory,
all subscribe to the thesis that there are at least some laws that depend for
their "authority" not on some pre-existing human convention, but on
the logical relationship in which they stand to moral standards. Otherwise put,
some norms are authoritative in virtue of their moral content, even when there
is no convention that makes moral merit a criterion of legal validity. The idea
that the concepts of law and morality intersect in some way is called the
Overlap Thesis.
As an empirical matter, many natural law moral
theorists are also natural law legal theorists, but the two theories, strictly
speaking, are logically independent. One can deny natural law theory of law but
hold a natural law theory of morality. John Austin, the most influential of the
early legal positivists, for example, denied the Overlap Thesis but held
something that resembles a natural law ethical theory.
Indeed, Austin explicitly endorsed the view that
it is not necessarily true that the legal validity of a norm depends on whether
its content conforms to morality. But while Austin thus denied the Overlap
Thesis, he accepted an objectivist moral theory; indeed, Austin inherited his
utilitarianism almost wholesale from J.S. Mill and Jeremy Bentham. Here it is
worth noting that utilitarians sometimes seem to suggest that they derive their
utilitarianism from certain facts about human nature; as Bentham once wrote,
"nature has placed mankind under the governance of two sovereign masters,
pain and pleasure. It is for them alone to point out what we ought to do, as
well as to determine what we shall do. On the one hand the standard of right
and wrong, on the other the chain of causes and effects, are fastened to their
throne" (Bentham 1948, 1). Thus, a commitment to natural law theory of
morality is consistent with the denial of natural law theory of law.
Conversely, one could, though this would be
unusual, accept a natural law theory of law without holding a natural law
theory of morality. One could, for example, hold that the conceptual point of
law is, in part, to reproduce the demands of morality, but also hold a form of
ethical subjectivism (or relativism). On this peculiar view, the conceptual
point of law would be to enforce those standards that are morally valid in
virtue of cultural consensus. For this reason, natural law theory of law is
logically independent of natural law theory of morality. The remainder of this
essay will be exclusively concerned with natural law theories of law.
II.
Conceptual Naturalism
II.1 The Project of Conceptual Jurisprudence
The principal objective of conceptual (or
analytic) jurisprudence has traditionally been to provide an account of what
distinguishes law as a system of norms from other systems of norms, such as
ethical norms. As John Austin describes the project, conceptual jurisprudence seeks
"the essence or nature which is common to all laws that are properly so
called" (Austin 1995, 11). Accordingly, the task of conceptual
jurisprudence is to provide a set of necessary and sufficient conditions for
the existence of law that distinguishes law from non-law in every possible
world.
While this task is usually interpreted as an
attempt to analyze the concepts of law and legal system, there is some
confusion as to both the value and character of conceptual analysis in
philosophy of law. As Brian Leiter (1998) points out, philosophy of law is one
of the few philosophical disciplines that takes conceptual analysis as its
principal concern; most other areas in philosophy have taken a naturalistic
turn, incorporating the tools and methods of the sciences. To clarify the role
of conceptual analysis in law, Brian Bix (1995) distinguishes a number of
different purposes that can be served by conceptual claims: (1) to track
linguistic usage; (2) to stipulate meanings; (3) to explain what is important or
essential about a class of objects; and (4) to establish an evaluative test for
the concept-word. Bix takes conceptual analysis in law to be primarily
concerned with (3) and (4).
In any event, conceptual analysis of law remains
an important, if controversial, project in contemporary legal theory.
Conceptual theories of law have traditionally been characterized in terms of
their posture towards the Overlap Thesis. Thus, conceptual theories of law have
traditionally been divided into two main categories: those like natural law
legal theory that affirm there is a conceptual relation between law and
morality and those like legal positivism that deny such a relation.
II.2 Classical Natural Law Theory
All forms of natural law theory subscribe to the
Overlap Thesis, which asserts that there is some kind of non-conventional
relation between law and morality. According to this view, then, the notion of
law cannot be fully articulated without some reference to moral notions. Though
the Overlap Thesis may seem unambiguous, there are a number of different ways
in which it can be interpreted.
The strongest construction of the Overlap Thesis
forms the foundation for the classical naturalism of Aquinas and Blackstone.
Aquinas distinguishes four kinds of law: (1) eternal law; (2) natural law; (3)
human law; and (4) divine law. Eternal law is comprised of those laws that
govern the nature of an eternal universe; as Susan Dimock (1999, 22) puts it,
one can "think of eternal law as comprising all those scientific (physical,
chemical, biological, psychological, etc.) 'laws' by which the universe is
ordered." Divine law is concerned with those standards that must be
satisfied by a human being to achieve eternal salvation. One cannot discover
divine law by natural reason alone; the precepts of divine law are disclosed
only through divine revelation.
The natural law is comprised of those precepts of
the eternal law that govern the behavior of beings possessing reason and free
will. The first precept of the natural law, according to Aquinas, is the
somewhat vacuous imperative to do good and avoid evil. Here it is worth noting
that Aquinas holds a natural law theory of morality: what is good and evil,
according to Aquinas, is derived from the rational nature of human beings. Good
and evil are thus both objective and universal.
But Aquinas is also a natural law legal theorist.
On his view, a human law (i.e., that which is promulgated by human beings) is
valid only insofar as its content conforms to the content of the natural law;
as Aquinas puts the point: "[E]very human law has just so much of the
nature of law as is derived from the law of nature. But if in any point it
deflects from the law of nature, it is no longer a law but a perversion of
law" (ST I-II, Q.95, A.II). To paraphrase Augustine's famous remark, an
unjust law is really no law at all.
The idea that a norm that does not conform to the
natural law cannot be legally valid is the defining thesis of conceptual
naturalism. As William Blackstone describes the thesis, "This law of
nature, being co-eval with mankind and dictated by God himself, is of course
superior in obligation to any other. It is binding over all the globe, in all
countries, and at all times: no human laws are of any validity, if contrary to
this; and such of them as are valid derive all their force, and all their
authority, mediately or immediately, from this original" (1979, 41). In
this passage, Blackstone articulates the two claims that constitute the
theoretical core of conceptual naturalism: 1) there can be no legally valid
standards that conflict with the natural law; and 2) all valid laws derive what
force and authority they have from the natural law.
It should be noted that classical naturalism is
consistent with allowing a substantial role to human beings in the manufacture
of law. While the classical naturalist seems committed to the claim that the
law necessarily incorporates all moral principles, this claim does not imply
that the law is exhausted by the set of moral principles. There will still be
coordination problems (e.g., which side of the road to drive on) that can be
resolved in any number of ways consistent with the set of moral principles.
Thus, the classical naturalist does not deny that human beings have
considerable discretion in creating natural law. Rather she claims only that
such discretion is necessarily limited by moral norms: legal norms that are
promulgated by human beings are valid only if they are consistent with
morality.
Critics of conceptual naturalism have raised a
number of objections to this view. First, it has often been pointed out that, contra Augustine, unjust laws are
all-too- frequently enforced against persons. As Austin petulantly put the
point:
Now, to say that human laws which
conflict with the Divine law are not binding, that is to say, are not laws, is
to talk stark nonsense. The most pernicious laws, and therefore those which are
most opposed to the will of God, have been and are continually enforced as laws
by judicial tribunals. Suppose an act innocuous, or positively beneficial, be
prohibited by the sovereign under the penalty of death; if I commit this act, I
shall be tried and condemned, and if I object to the sentence, that it is
contrary to the law of God, who has commanded that human lawgivers shall not
prohibit acts which have no evil consequences, the Court of Justice will
demonstrate the inconclusiveness of my reasoning by hanging me up, in pursuance
of the law of which I have impugned the validity (Austin 1995, 158).
Of course, as Brian Bix (1999) points out, the
argument does little work for Austin because it is always possible for a court
to enforce a law against a person that does not satisfy Austin's own theory of
legal validity.
Another frequently expressed worry is that
conceptual naturalism undermines the possibility of moral criticism of the law;
inasmuch as conformity with natural law is a necessary condition for legal
validity, all valid law is, by definition, morally just. Thus, on this line of
reasoning, the legal validity of a norm necessarily entails its moral justice.
As Jules Coleman and Jeffrey Murphy (1990, 18) put the point:
The important things [conceptual
naturalism] supposedly allows us to do (e.g., morally evaluate the law and
determine our moral obligations with respect to the law) are actually rendered
more difficult by its collapse of the distinction between morality and law. If
we really want to think about the law from the moral point of view, it may
obscure the task if we see law and morality as essentially linked in some way.
Moral criticism and reform of law may be aided by an initial moral skepticism
about the law.
There are a couple of problems with this line of
objection. First, conceptual naturalism does not foreclose criticism of those
norms that are being enforced by a society as law. Insofar as it can plausibly
be claimed that the content of a norm being enforced by society as law does not
conform to the natural law, this is a legitimate ground of moral criticism:
given that the norm being enforced by law is unjust, it follows, according to
conceptual naturalism, that it is not legally valid. Thus, the state commits
wrong by enforcing that norm against private citizens.
Second, and more importantly, this line of
objection seeks to criticize a conceptual theory of law by pointing to its
practical implications ñ a strategy that seems to commit a category mistake.
Conceptual jurisprudence assumes the existence of a core of social practices
(constituting law) that requires a conceptual explanation. The project motivating
conceptual jurisprudence, then, is to articulate the concept of law in a way
that accounts for these pre-existing social practices. A conceptual theory of
law can legitimately be criticized for its failure to adequately account for
the pre-existing data, as it were; but it cannot legitimately be criticized for
either its normative quality or its practical implications.
A more interesting line of argument has recently
been taken up by Brian Bix (1996). Following John Finnis (1980), Bix rejects
the interpretation of Aquinas and Blackstone as conceptual naturalists, arguing
instead that the claim that an unjust law is not a law should not be taken
literally:
A more reasonable interpretation of
statements like "an unjust law is no law at all" is that unjust laws
are not laws "in the fullest sense." As we might say of some
professional, who had the necessary degrees and credentials, but seemed
nonetheless to lack the necessary ability or judgment: "she's no
lawyer" or "he's no doctor." This only indicates that we do not
think that the title in this case carries with it all the implications it
usually does. Similarly, to say that an unjust law is "not really
law" may only be to point out that it does not carry the same moral force
or offer the same reasons for action as laws consistent with "higher
law" (Bix 1996, 226).
Thus, Bix construes Aquinas and Blackstone as
having views more similar to the neo- naturalism of John Finnis discussed below
in Section III. Nevertheless, while a plausible case can be made in favor of
Bix's view, the long history of construing Aquinas and Blackstone as conceptual
naturalists, along with its pedagogical value in developing other theories of
law, ensures that this practice is likely, for better or worse, to continue
indefinitely.
III.
The Substantive Neo-Naturalism of John Finnis
John Finnis takes himself to be explicating and
developing the views of Aquinas and Blackstone. Like Bix, Finnis believes that
the naturalism of Aquinas and Blackstone should not be construed as a conceptual
account of the existence conditions for law. According to Finnis, the classical
naturalists were not concerned with giving a conceptual account of legal
validity; rather they were concerned with explaining the moral force of law:
"the principles of natural law explain the obligatory force (in the
fullest sense of 'obligation') of positive laws, even when those laws cannot be
deduced from those principles" (Finnis 1980, 23-24). On Finnis's view of
the Overlap Thesis, the essential function of law is to provide a justification
for state coercion (a view he shares with Ronald Dworkin). Accordingly, an
unjust law can be legally valid, but it cannot provide an adequate
justification for use of the state coercive power and is hence not obligatory
in the fullest sense; thus, an unjust law fails to realize the moral ideals
implicit in the concept of law. An unjust law, on this view, is legally
binding, but is not fully law.
Like classical naturalism, Finnis's naturalism is
both an ethical theory and a theory of law. Finnis distinguishes a number of
equally valuable basic goods: life, health, knowledge, play, friendship,
religion, and aesthetic experience. Each of these goods, according to Finnis,
has intrinsic value in the sense that it should, given human nature, be valued
for its own sake and not merely for the sake of some other good it can assist
in bringing about. Moreover, each of these goods is universal in the sense that
it governs all human cultures at all times. The point of moral principles, on
this view, is to give ethical structure to the pursuit of these basic goods;
moral principles enable us to select among competing goods and to define what a
human being can permissibly do in pursuit of a basic good.
On Finnis's view, the conceptual point of law is
to facilitate the common good by providing authoritative rules that solve
coordination problems that arise in connection with the common pursuit of these
basic goods. Thus, Finnis sums up his theory of law as follows:
[T]he term 'law' ... refer[s] primarily
to rules made, in accordance with regulative legal rules, by a determinate and
effective authority (itself identified and, standardly, constituted as an
institution by legal rules) for a 'complete' community, and buttressed by
sanctions in accordance with the rule-guided stipulations of adjudicative
institutions, this ensemble of rules and institutions being directed to
reasonably resolving any of the community's co-ordination problems (and to
ratifying, tolerating, regulating, or overriding co-ordination solutions from
any other institutions or sources of norms) for the common good of that
community (Finnis 1980, 276).
Again, it bears emphasizing that Finnis takes
care to deny that there is any necessary moral test for legal validity:
"one would simply be misunderstanding my conception of the nature and
purpose of explanatory definitions of theoretical concepts if one supposed that
my definition 'ruled out as non-laws' laws which failed to meet, or meet fully,
one or other of the elements of the definition" (Finnis 1980, 278).
Nevertheless, Finnis believes that to the extent
that a norm fails to satisfy these conditions, it likewise fails to fully
manifest the nature of law and thereby fails to fully obligate the
citizen-subject of the law. Unjust laws may obligate in a technical legal
sense, on Finnis's view, but they may fail to provide moral reasons for action
of the sort that it is the point of legal authority to provide. Thus, Finnis
argues that "a ruler's use of authority is radically defective if he
exploits his opportunities by making stipulations intended by him not for the
common good but for his own or his friends' or party's or faction's advantage,
or out of malice against some person or group" (Finnis 1980, 352). For the
ultimate basis of a ruler's moral authority, on this view, "is the fact
that he has the opportunity, and thus the responsibility, of furthering the
common good by stipulating solutions to a community's co- ordination
problems" (Finnis 1980, 351).
Finnis's theory is certainly more plausible as a
theory of law than the traditional interpretation of classical naturalism, but
such plausibility comes, for better or worse, at the expense of naturalism's
identity as a distinct theory of law. Indeed, it appears that Finnis's natural
law theory is compatible with naturalism's historical adversary, legal
positivism, inasmuch as Finnis's view is compatible with a source-based theory
of legal validity; laws that are technically valid in virtue of source but
unjust do not, according to Finnis, fully obligate the citizen. Indeed, Finnis
(1996) believes that Aquinas's classical naturalism fully affirms the notion
that human laws are "posited."
IV. The
Procedural Naturalism of Lon L. Fuller
Like Finnis, Lon Fuller (1964) rejects the
conceptual naturalist idea that there are necessary substantive moral constraints on the content of law. But Fuller,
unlike Finnis, believes that law is necessarily subject to a procedural morality. On Fuller's view,
human activity is necessarily goal-oriented or purposive in the sense that
people engage in a particular activity because it helps them to achieve some
end. Insofar as human activity is essentially purposive, according to Fuller,
particular human activities can be understood only in terms that make reference
to their purposes and ends. Thus, since lawmaking is essentially purposive
activity, it can be understood only in terms that explicitly acknowledge its
essential values and purposes:
The only formula that might be
called a definition of law offered in these writings is by now thoroughly
familiar: law is the enterprise of subjecting human conduct to the governance
of rules. Unlike most modern theories of law, this view treats law as an
activity and regards a legal system as the product of a sustained purposive
effort (Fuller 1964, 106).
To the extent that a definition of law can be
given, then, it must include the idea that law's essential function is to
"achiev[e] Ö [social] order Ö through subjecting people's conduct to the
guidance of general rules by which they may themselves orient their
behavior" (Fuller 1965, 657).
Fuller's functionalist conception of law implies
that nothing can count as law unless it is capable of performing law's
essential function of guiding behavior. And to be capable of performing this
function, a system of rules must satisfy the following principles: (P1) the
rules must be expressed in general terms; (P2) the rules must be publicly promulgated;
(P3) the rules must be prospective in effect; (P4) the rules must be expressed
in understandable terms; (P5) the rules must be consistent with one another;
(P6) the rules must not require conduct beyond the powers of the affected
parties; (P7) the rules must not be changed so frequently that the subject
cannot rely on them; and (P8) the rules must be administered in a manner
consistent with their wording.
On Fuller's view, no system of rules that fails
minimally to satisfy these principles of legality can achieve law's essential
purpose of achieving social order through the use of rules that guide behavior.
A system of rules that fails to satisfy (P2) or (P4), for example, cannot guide
behavior because people will not be able to determine what the rules require.
Accordingly, Fuller concludes that his eight principles are
"internal" to law in the sense that they are built into the existence
conditions for law.
These internal principles constitute a morality,
according to Fuller, because law necessarily has positive moral value in two
respects: (1) law conduces to a state of social order and (2) does so by
respecting human autonomy because rules guide behavior. Since no system of
rules can achieve these morally valuable objectives without minimally complying
with the principles of legality, it follows, on Fuller's view, that they
constitute a morality. Since these moral principles are built into the
existence conditions for law, they are internal and hence represent a
conceptual connection between law and morality. Thus, like the classical
naturalists and unlike Finnis, Fuller subscribes to the strongest form of the
Overlap Thesis, which makes him a conceptual naturalist.
Nevertheless, Fuller's conceptual naturalism is
fundamentally different from that of classical naturalism. First, Fuller
rejects the classical naturalist view that there are necessary moral
constraints on the content of law, holding instead that there are necessary
moral constraints on the procedural mechanisms by which law is made and
administered: "What I have called the internal morality of law is ... a
procedural version of natural law ... [in the sense that it is] concerned, not
with the substantive aims of legal rules, but with the ways in which a system
of rules for governing human conduct must be constructed and administered if it
is to be efficacious and at the same time remain what it purports to be"
(Fuller 1964, 96- 97).
Second, Fuller identifies the conceptual
connection between law and morality at a higher level of abstraction than the
classical naturalists. The classical naturalists view morality as providing
substantive constraints on the content of individual laws; an unjust norm, on
this view, is conceptually disqualified from being legally valid. In contrast,
Fuller views morality as providing a constraint on the existence of a legal
system: "A total failure in any one of these eight directions does not
simply result in a bad system of law; it results in something that is not
properly called a legal system at all" (Fuller 1964, 39).
Fuller's procedural naturalism is vulnerable to a
number of objections. H.L.A. Hart, for example, denies Fuller's claim that the
principles of legality constitute an internal morality; according to Hart,
Fuller confuses the notions of morality and efficacy:
[T]he author's insistence on
classifying these principles of legality as a "morality" is a source
of confusion both for him and his readers.... [T]he crucial objection to the
designation of these principles of good legal craftsmanship as morality, in
spite of the qualification "inner," is that it perpetrates a
confusion between two notions that it is vital to hold apart: the notions of
purposive activity and morality. Poisoning is no doubt a purposive activity,
and reflections on its purpose may show that it has its internal principles.
("Avoid poisons however lethal if they cause the victim to
vomit"....) But to call these principles of the poisoner's art "the
morality of poisoning" would simply blur the distinction between the
notion of efficiency for a purpose and those final judgments about activities
and purposes with which morality in its various forms is concerned (Hart 1965,
1285-86).
On Hart's view, all actions, including virtuous
acts like lawmaking and impermissible acts like poisoning, have their own
internal standards of efficacy. But insofar as such standards of efficacy
conflict with morality, as they do in the case of poisoning, it follows that
they are distinct from moral standards. Thus, while Hart concedes that
something like Fuller's eight principles are built into the existence
conditions for law, he concludes they do not constitute a conceptual connection
between law and morality.
Unfortunately, Hart overlooks the fact that most
of Fuller's eight principles double as moral ideals of fairness. For example,
public promulgation in understandable terms may be a necessary condition for
efficacy, but it is also a moral ideal; it is morally objectionable for a state
to enforce rules that have not been publicly promulgated in terms reasonably
calculated to give notice of what is required. Similarly, we take it for
granted that it is wrong for a state to enact retroactive rules, inconsistent
rules, and rules that require what is impossible. Poisoning may have its
internal standards of efficacy, but such standards are distinguishable from the
principles of legality in that they conflict with moral ideals.
Nevertheless, Fuller's principles operate
internally, not as moral ideals, but merely as principles of efficacy. As
Fuller would likely acknowledge, the existence of a legal system is consistent
with considerable divergence from the principles of legality. Legal standards,
for example, are necessarily promulgated in general terms that inevitably give
rise to problems of vagueness. And officials all too often fail to administer
the laws in a fair and even-handed manneróeven in the best of legal systems.
These divergences may always be prima
facie objectionable, but they are inconsistent with a legal system only
when they render a legal system incapable of performing its essential function
of guiding behavior. Insofar as these principles are built into the existence
conditions for law, it is because they operate as efficacy conditionsóand not
because they function as moral ideals.
Ronald
Dworkin's "Third Theory"
Ronald Dworkin's so-called third theory of law is
best understood as a response to legal positivism, which is essentially
constituted by three theoretical commitments: the Social Fact Thesis, the
Conventionality Thesis, and the Separability Thesis. The Social Fact Thesis
asserts it is a necessary truth that legal validity is ultimately a function of
certain kinds of social facts; the idea here is that what ultimately explains
the validity of a law is the presence of certain social facts, especially
formal promulgation by a legislature.
The Conventionality Thesis emphasizes law's
conventional nature, claiming that the social facts giving rise to legal
validity are authoritative in virtue of a social convention. On this view, the
criteria that determine whether or not any given norm counts as a legal norm
are binding because of an implicit or explicit agreement among officials. Thus,
for example, the U.S. Constitution is authoritative in virtue of the
conventional fact that it was formally ratified by all fifty states.
The Separability Thesis, at the most general
level, simply denies naturalism's Overlap Thesis; according to the Separability
Thesis, there is no conceptual overlap between the notions of law and morality.
As Hart more narrowly construes it, the Separability Thesis is "just the
simple contention that it is in no sense a necessary truth that laws reproduce
or satisfy certain demands of morality, though in fact they have often done
so" (Hart 1994, 185-186).
Dworkin rejects positivism's Social Fact Thesis
on the ground that there are some legal standards the authority of which cannot
be explained in terms of social facts. In deciding hard cases, for example,
judges often invoke moral principles that Dworkin believes do not derive their legal authority from the social criteria
of legality contained in a rule of recognition (Dworkin 1977, p. 40).
In Riggs v.
Palmer, for example, the court considered the question of whether a
murderer could take under the will of his victim. At the time the case was
decided, neither the statutes nor the case law governing wills expressly
prohibited a murderer from taking under his victim's will. Despite this, the
court declined to award the defendant his gift under the will on the ground
that it would be wrong to allow him to profit from such a grievous wrong. On
Dworkin's view, the court decided the case by citing "the principle that
no man may profit from his own wrong as a background standard against which to
read the statute of wills and in this way justified a new interpretation of
that statute" (Dworkin 1977, 29).
On Dworkin's view, the Riggs court was not just reaching beyond the law to extralegal standards
when it considered this principle. For the Riggs
judges would "rightfully" have been criticized had they failed to
consider this principle; if it were merely an extralegal standard, there would
be no rightful grounds to criticize a failure to consider it (Dworkin 1977,
35). Accordingly, Dworkin concludes that the best explanation for the propriety
of such criticism is that principles are part of the law.
Further, Dworkin maintains that the legal
authority of standards like the Riggs
principle cannot derive from promulgation in accordance with purely formal
requirements: "[e]ven though principles draw support from the official
acts of legal institutions, they do not have a simple or direct enough
connection with these acts to frame that connection in terms of criteria
specified by some ultimate master rule of recognition" (Dworkin 1977, 41).
On Dworkin's view, the legal authority of the Riggs principle can be explained wholly
in terms of its content. The Riggs
principle was binding, in part, because it is a requirement of fundamental
fairness that figures into the best moral justification for a society's legal
practices considered as a whole. A moral principle is legally authoritative,
according to Dworkin, insofar as it maximally conduces to the best moral
justification for a society's legal practices considered as a whole.
Dworkin believes that a legal principle maximally
contributes to such a justification if and only if it satisfies two conditions:
(1) the principle coheres with existing legal materials; and (2) the principle
is the most morally attractive standard that satisfies (1). The correct legal
principle is the one that makes the law the moral best it can be. Accordingly,
on Dworkin's view, adjudication is and should be interpretive:
[J]udges should decide hard cases by
interpreting the political structure of their community in the following,
perhaps special way: by trying to find the best justification they can find, in
principles of political morality, for the structure as a whole, from the most
profound constitutional rules and arrangements to the details of, for example,
the private law of tort or contract (Dworkin 1982, 165).
There are, thus, two elements of a successful
interpretation. First, since an interpretation is successful insofar as it
justifies the particular practices of a particular society, the interpretation
must fit with those practices in the
sense that it coheres with existing legal materials defining the practices.
Second, since an interpretation provides a moral
justification for those practices, it must present them in the best
possible moral light.
For this reason, Dworkin argues that a judge
should strive to interpret a case in roughly the following way:
A thoughtful judge might establish
for himself, for example, a rough "threshold" of fit which any
interpretation of data must meet in order to be "acceptable" on the
dimension of fit, and then suppose that if more than one interpretation of some
part of the law meets this threshold, the choice among these should be made,
not through further and more precise comparisons between the two along that
dimension, but by choosing the interpretation which is
"substantively" better, that is, which better promotes the political
ideals he thinks correct (Dworkin 1982, 171).
As Dworkin conceives it, then, the judge must
approach judicial decision-making as something that resembles an exercise in
moral philosophy. Thus, for example, the judge must decide cases on the basis
of those moral principles that "figure[] in the soundest theory of law
that can be provided as a justification for the explicit substantive and
institutional rules of the jurisdiction in question" (Dworkin 1977, 66).
And this is a process, according to Dworkin, that
"must carry the lawyer very deep into political and moral theory."
Indeed, in later writings, Dworkin goes so far as to claim, somewhat
implausibly, that "any judge's opinion is itself a piece of legal
philosophy, even when the philosophy is hidden and the visible argument is
dominated by citation and lists of facts" (Dworkin 1986, 90).
Dworkin believes his theory of judicial
obligation is a consequence of what he calls the Rights Thesis, according to
which judicial decisions always enforce pre-existing rights: "even when no
settled rule disposes of the case, one party may nevertheless have a right to
win. It remains the judge's duty, even in hard cases, to discover what the
rights of the parties are, not to invent new rights retrospectively"
(Dworkin 1977, 81).
In "Hard Cases," Dworkin distinguishes
between two kinds of legal argument. Arguments of policy "justify a
political decision by showing that the decision advances or protects some
collective goal of the community as a whole" (Dworkin 1977, 82). In
contrast, arguments of principle "justify a political decision by showing
that the decision respects or secures some individual or group right"
(Dworkin 1977, 82).
On Dworkin's view, while the legislature may
legitimately enact laws that are justified by arguments of policy, courts may
not pursue such arguments in deciding cases. For a consequentialist argument of
policy can never provide an adequate justification for deciding in favor of one
party's claim of right and against another party's claim of right. An appeal to
a pre-existing right, according to Dworkin, can ultimately be justified only by
an argument of principle. Thus, insofar as judicial decisions necessarily
adjudicate claims of right, they must ultimately be based on the moral
principles that figure into the best justification of the legal practices
considered as a whole.
Notice that Dworkin's views on legal principles
and judicial obligation are inconsistent with all three of legal positivism's
core commitments. Each contradicts the Conventionality Thesis insofar as judges
are bound to interpret posited law in light of unposited moral principles. Each
contradicts the Social Fact Thesis because these moral principles count as part
of a community's law regardless of whether they have been formally promulgated.
Most importantly, Dworkin's view contradicts the Separability Thesis in that it
seems to imply that some norms are necessarily valid in virtue of their moral
content. It is his denial of the Separability Thesis that places Dworkin in the
naturalist camp.
Sources
Thomas Aquinas, On Law, Morality and Politics
(Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co., 1988)
John Austin, Lectures on Jurisprudence and the
Philosophy of Positive Law (St. Clair Shores, MI: Scholarly Press, 1977)
------The Province of Jurisprudence Determined
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995)
Jeremy Bentham, A Fragment of Government
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988)
------Of Laws In General (London: Athlone Press,
1970)
------The Principles of Morals and Legislation
(New York: Hafner Press, 1948)
Brian Bix, "On Description and Legal
Reasoning," in Linda Meyer (ed.), Rules and Reasoning (Oxford: Hart
Publishing, 1999)
------Jurisprudence: Theory and Context (Boulder,
CO: Westview Press, 1996)
------"Natural Law Theory," in Dennis M.
Patterson (ed.), A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory
(Cambridge: Blackwell Publishing Co., 1996)
William Blackstone, Commentaries on the Law of
England (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1979)
Jules L. Coleman, "On the Relationship Between
Law and Morality," Ratio Juris,
vol. 2, no. 1 (1989), 66-78
------"Negative and Positive Positivism," 11
Journal of Legal Studies 139 (1982)
Jules L. Coleman and Jeffrie Murphy, Philosophy of
Law (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1990)
Ronald M. Dworkin, Law's Empire (Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1986)
------Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1977)
John Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980)
------"The Truth in Legal Positivism," in
Robert P. George, The Autonomy of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996),
195-214
Lon L. Fuller, The Morality of Law, Revised
Edition (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1964)
------"A Reply to Professors Cohen and
Dworkin", 10 Villanova Law Review
655 (1965), 657.
------"Positivism and Fidelity to Law--A Reply to
Professor Hart," 71 Harvard Law
Review 630 (1958)
Klaus F¸Ã¾er, "Farewell to 'Legal Positivism': The
Separation Thesis Unravelling," in George, The Autonomy of Law,
119-162
Robert P. George, "Natural Law and Positive
Law," in George, The Autonomy of Law, 321-334
------Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992)
H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law, Second Edition
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994)
------"Book Review of The Morality of Law"
78 Harvard Law Review 1281 (1965)
------Essays on Bentham (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1982)
------"Positivism and the Separation of Law and
Morals," 71 Harvard Law Review
593 (1958)
Kenneth Einar Himma, "Positivism, Naturalism, and
the Obligation to Obey Law," Southern
Journal of Philosophy, vol. 36, no. 2 (Summer 1999)
------"Functionalism and Legal Theory: The
Hart/Fuller Debate Revisited," De
Philosophia, vol. 14, no. 2 (Fall/Winter 1998)
J.L. Mackie, "The Third Theory of Law," Philosophy & Public Affairs, Vol. 7,
No. 1 (Fall 1977)
Michael Moore, "Law as a Functional Kind,"
in George, Natural Law Theory, 188- 242
Joseph Raz, The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and
Morality (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979)
------"Authority, Law and Morality," The Monist, vol. 68, 295-324
------"Legal Principles and the Limits of
Law," 81 Yale Law Review 823
(1972)
Geoffrey Sayre-McCord, "The Many Moral
Realisms," in Sayre-McCord (ed.), Essays on Moral Realism (Ithica:
Cornell University Press, 1988)
An Overview of Natural Law Theory
by
Jonathan Dolhenty, Ph.D.
Natural law theory is one of the most
important theories in the philosophy of Classical Realism. It is also widely
misunderstood by many who have either not taken the time to study it or have
heard of it and dismissed it as a "medieval" relic. What I want to do
here is merely sketch out a general presentation of natural law theory, with
the hope that the reader will become interested enough to pursue further study
of it. I will provide a link to more in-depth resources at the end of this
essay.
Before we get into an overview of the nature of
natural law theory itself, let's take a brief look at some history.
The concept of natural law has taken several
forms. The idea began with the ancient Greeks' conception of a universe
governed in every particular by an eternal, immutable law and in their
distinction between what is just by nature and just by convention. Stoicism
provided the most complete classical formulation of natural law. The Stoics
argued that the universe is governed by reason, or rational principle; they
further argued that all humans have reason within them and can therefore know
and obey its law. Because human beings have the faculty of choice (a free
will), they will not necessarily obey the law; if they act in accordance with
reason, however, they will be "following nature."
Christian philosophers readily adapted Stoic
natural law theory, identifying natural law with the law of God. For Thomas
Aquinas, natural law is that part of the eternal law of God ("the reason
of divine wisdom") which is knowable by human beings by means of their
powers of reason. Human, or positive, law is the application of natural law to
particular social circumstances. Like the Stoics, Aquinas believed that a
positive law that violates natural law is not true law.
With the secularization of society resulting from
the Renaissance and Reformation, natural law theory found a new basis in human
reason. The 17th-century Dutch jurist Hugo Grotius believed that humans by
nature are not only reasonable but social. Thus the rules that are
"natural" to them -- those dictated by reason alone -- are those
which enable them to live in harmony with one another. From this argument, by
the way, Grotius developed the first comprehensive theory of international law.
Natural law theory eventually gave rise to a
concept of "natural rights." John Locke argued that human beings in
the state of nature are free and equal, yet insecure in their freedom. When
they enter society they surrender only such rights as are necessary for their
security and for the common good. Each individual retains fundamental
prerogatives drawn from natural law relating to the integrity of person and
property (natural rights). This natural rights theory provided a philosophical
basis for both the American and French revolutions. Thomas Jefferson used the
natural law theory to justify his trinity of "inalienable rights"
which were stated in the United States Declaration of Independence.
During the 19th century natural law theory lost
influence as utilitarianism and Benthamism, positivism, materialism, and the
historical school of jurisprudence became dominant. In the 20th century,
however, natural law theory has received new attention, partly in reaction to
the rise of totalitarianism and an increased interest in human rights
throughout the world. With this contemporary interest in mind, let's now turn to
our attention to the natural law theory as understood by the tradition of
Classical Realism.
What do we mean by "natural law"? In
its simplest definition, natural law is that "unwritten law" that is
more or less the same for everyone everywhere. To be more exact, natural law is
the concept of a body of moral principles that is common to all humankind and,
as generally posited, is recognizable by human reason alone. Natural law is
therefore distinguished from -- and provides a standard for -- positive law, the
formal legal enactments of a particular society.
Since law must always be some dictate of reason,
natural law also will be some dictate of reason. In fact, it is law discovered
by human reason. Our normal and natural grasp of the natural law is effected by
reason, that is, by the thinking mind, and in this service reason is sometimes
called "conscience." We, in all our human acts, inevitably see them
in their relation to the natural law, and we mentally pronounce upon their
agreement or disagreement with the natural law. Such a pronouncement may be
called a "judgment of conscience." The "norm" of morality
is the natural law as applied by conscience. Lastly, we can say that the
natural law is the disposition of things as known by our human reason and to which
we must conform ourselves if we are to realize our proper end or
"good" as human beings.
To sum it
up, then, we can say that the natural law:
- is not made by human beings;
- is based on the structure of reality itself;
- is the same for all human beings and at all times;
- is an unchanging rule or pattern which is there for human beings to discover;
- is the naturally knowable moral law;
- is a means by which human beings can rationally guide themselves to their good.
It is interesting to note that virtually everyone
seems to have some knowledge of natural law even before such knowledge is
codified and formalized. Even young children make an appeal to "fair
play," demand that things be "fair and square," and older
children and adults often apply the "golden rule." When doing so,
they are spontaneously invoking the natural law. This is why many proponents of
the natural law theory say it is the law which is "written upon the hearts
of men." These are examples of what is called "connatural
knowledge," that is, a knowledge which:
- follows on the "lived experience" of the truth;
- is the living contact of the intellect with reality itself;
- is not always given expression in concepts;
- may be obscure to the knower;
- is overlaid with elements from the affective or feeling side of man's nature.
Now, our reflection on our own conduct gives rise
to the explicit formulation of the precepts of the natural law. We as human
beings put our "commonsense" notions of natural law under
"critical examination." In other words, our natural impulses toward
"fair play," justice, and so on are subject to a rigorous
investigation and rationalization. And our understanding of natural law becomes
more precise as we consider and codify the principles or precepts of natural
law. The primary precept of natural law will be the most basic principle about
human action that can be formulated.
Those readers familiar with Classical Realism
will recall that there is an absolutely first and indemonstrable principle in
the speculative order of things. That is, there is an absolutely basic,
self-evident truth of reality upon which we build our entire metaphysics which
serves as the foundation for our view of the ultimate structure of reality.
This is the Principle of Contradiction, from which we derive other basic
principles such as Identity and Excluded Middle. Strictly speaking, the
Principle of Contradiction cannot be "proved." It must be accepted as
an absolute "intuitive" or self-evident truth, the truth of which is
shown by an analysis of the terms of the Principle and the impossibility of
thinking the opposite.
Natural law theory is of the "practical
order" of things and the first principle of the practical order is a
principle that directs human acts in all their operations, and it will be
concerned with the "good," since we act in terms of what a least
seems good to us. Therefore, the primary principle of the practical order --
the first precept of natural law -- is a formulation based upon the notion of
the good and is stated in the following way: The "good" (according to
reason) must be done, and evil (what is contrary to reason) must be avoided.
The simplest statement of this precept is, of course, "Do good and avoid
evil."
Although we rarely express the precept of
"Do good and avoid evil" explicitly (just as we rarely state the
Principle of Contradiction explicitly in daily life), nevertheless we always
act in terms of such a precept. This fact points to the fundamental truth of
such a precept, and indicates how it expresses something "natural" to
human beings. A human being naturally inclines to seek what appears good to
reason, and naturally shrinks from what appears to be evil. Hence, the
justification of speaking of this basic moral law as "natural" law.
Upon further reflection, we can distinguish,
within natural law, primary and secondary precepts. The primary precepts will
correspond to the order of natural inclinations in human beings. The most
fundamental inclination of all, "Do good and avoid evil," will give
rise to other primary precepts such as the natural inclination to
self-preservation, to live in society, to avoid harm to others, and to know
truths about the reality we live in and our own human nature. These primary
precepts are unchangeable to the extent they concern the primary ends of the
natural inclinations inherent in all human beings.
The primary precepts are very general in their
formulation. The secondary precepts, on the other hand, are more particular or
specific and are concerned with things to which we are not inclined so
immediately. Among these are such precepts as those regarding the education of
children, and the stability of family life, and the demands of hospitality. On
the negative side, we also have secondary precepts regarding the neglect of
children, deliberate injury to others, and so on.
Do we know everything about the natural law? This
is a common question asked and a good one. The answer is a simple
"No." The discovery of the natural law is a continuously unfolding
enterprise. Just as it took human beings a long time to separate out and
clarify the laws of physical nature, so too for the laws of moral nature. The
passage of time and additional philosophical reflection always raises new
issues in natural law theory. For instance, slavery was once accepted as normal
and natural even by many who subscribed to natural law theory. We now know that
slavery violates the natural law. Society once accepted judicial torture as
being normal and natural. We now know that judicial slavery violates the
natural law. And, personally, I am convinced that one day our society will
"discover" that capital punishment violates natural law and we will
abolish it.
The obvious conclusion here is that our knowledge
of natural law, particularly regarding its secondary precepts, is incomplete,
and probably will always be incomplete. We, as civilized and rational human
beings, will always be involved in a "critical examination" of our
actions in the practical order. Out of this reflection will come new and
refined "truths" regarding ethics and moral philosophy. In fact, I
suspect that we are now in a time when the most important decisions we make as
a society will be those in ethics and moral philosophy (think
"bioethics" and "weapons of mass destruction"). This is one
reason why I have no reservations about suggesting that all students in our
institutions of higher education need a good dose of philosophical studies,
especially, of course, in the tradition of Classical Realism.
I hope you have some general knowledge of natural
law theory as a result of this brief overview. Moreover, I hope I have
interested you to seek more knowledge about this fascinating theory.
If you want to learn more, I have suggested some
resources which should help you in your investigation.
Thomas Hobbes and John Locke
Thomas Hobbes and John Locke, where they agreed and disagreed concerning nature, natural law, and the nature of man in a state of war.
Thomas Hobbes and John Locke were two main political philosophers during
the seventeenth century. Hobbes is the well known author of Leviathan, and
Locke is the author of An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. In their
essays, both men address the characteristics of man, natural law, and the
purpose and structure of government. The two men have very different opinions
of the characteristics of man. Hobbes sees man as being evil, whereas Locke
views man in a much more optimistic light. They both agree that all men are
equal according to natural law. However, their ideas of natural law differ
greatly. Hobbes sees natural law as a state of war in which every man is a
enemy to every man. Locke on the other hand, sees natural law as a state of
equality and freedom. Locke therefore believes that government is necessary
in order to preserve natural law, and on the contrary, Hobbes sees government
as necessary in order to control natural law. Hobbes and Locke see mankinds natural characteristics in two very different ways. Hobbes describes the life of man as solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short. He obviously does not think very highly man. He also says that it is hard for men to believe there be many so wise as themselves, expressing his discontent with how selfish men are. Conversely, Locke views mankinds natural characteristics much more optimistically. Locke sees men as being governed according to reason. He perceives men to be thinking, capable individuals that can coexist peacefully. Hobbes and Locke disagree on mankinds natural characteristics, but the degree of their disagreement grows much larger with respect to natural law. The main thing that Hobbes and Locke can seem to agree on, with respect to natural law, is that all men are equal in nature. For Hobbes, this equality exists in a state of war, in which every man has a right to every thing. He terms this state of war, a state of equality, because even the weakest has strength enough to kill the strongest. In Hobbess opinion, no one is superior, because they are all equal in their level of rottenness. Locke agrees that in natural law, no one is superior. However he writes, the state all men are naturally inis a state of perfect freedom equality and liberty, displaying his belief that men are sensible by nature, and can exist happily according to natural law, without the need for constant war. Locke does admit that war is sometimes necessary, but that one may only destroy a man who makes war upon him. In general, he believes that it is beneficial for humans to follow natural law. Since natural law is good, and not evil for Locke, it is therefore the role of government to preserve natural law. For Hobbes on the other hand, government must exist in order to control natural law. Hobbes reasons that people will abide by the laws the government sets, for fear of some evil consequence. Hobbes points out the selfish reasons for why man will follow government in order to explain how government is able to work, with men being so naturally evil. Locke sees government, as merely a preservation of that which is already good. Locke believes that people are willing to unite under a form of government so as to preserve their lives, liberties and estates, or in other words, their property. Since natural law is already good, government not only preserves natural law, but also works to enhance it. The ideas presented by Hobbes and Locke are often in opposition. Hobbes tends to take a much more pessimistic stance; viewing men as evil, natural law as a state of war, and government as something that can wipe out natural law. Locke takes a much more optimistic stance; viewing men as free and equal and seeing government as only a preservation of the state they are naturally in. Despite the difference in their arguments, their ideas were revolutionary for their time. The interest they took in mans natural characteristics, natural law, and the role of government, provided inspiration for, and was the focus of many literary works throughout the Enlightenment. |
Marxist
Jurisprudence
Tutor:
Chris Behrens
Student:
David Risstrom: 9106105
In the social production of their existence,
men inevitably enter into definite relations, which are independent of their
will, namely relations of production appropriate to a given stage in the
development of their material forces of production. The totality of these relations constitute the
economic structure of society, the real foundation, on which arises a legal and
political superstructure and to which correspond definite forms of social
consciousness.
Karl
Marx, Preface to A Contribution to the
Critique of Political Economy, 521.[1]
Marxist jurisprudence posits that
legal relations are determined by the economic base of particular kinds of
society and modes of production.[2] Marxist thought’s primary focus rests on
political economy and the corresponding power relations within society,
providing the most extensive critique to date of liberal tradition on which
many of our legal presuppositions are founded.
To this end, this essay examines law, its structure, motivation and
consequences for justice and rights from a Marxian jurisprudential perspective.
Marxism and Law
Your ideas are but the outgrowth of the conditions
of your bourgeois production and bourgeois property, just as your jurisprudence
is but the will of your class made into a law for all, a will, whose essential
character and direction are determined by the economical conditions of
existence in your class.
Karl
Marx, The Communist Manifesto, 24.
Law is not of central concern to
Marxists jurisprudentialists, as law in the capitalist mode of production is
seen as an instrument of class oppression perpetuated as a consequence of its
particular historical, social and economic structures. Indeed, wishing to avoid liberal
predisposition towards legal fetishism, Marxists deny the degree of importance
jurisprudence typically affords law in analyses of the composition and
determination of social formations.[3]
What is Marxism?
Marxist theories of political
economy, expounded upon the notions of Karl Marx (1818-83) and Friedrich Engels
(1820-95), consider law an instrument of class oppression that benefits the
ruling class through oppression of the proletariat. The common law system of criminal and civil
law, which protects personal and private property rights, as well as
facilitating predicability in social life, is regarded as “no more than a
system of coercion designed to protect bourgeois ownership of the means of
production”.[4]
Yet, despite Marx and Engels’
failure to develop a systematic approach to law[5],
and claims of failure in Eastern Europe and the Soviet Union, Marxism’s
materialist emphasis, particularly concerning the notion of alienation and its
consequences as outlined by Ollman[6],
assists its contemporary paucity.[7]
Historical Materialism
Men have history because they must produce
their life, and because they must produce it moreover in a certain way: this is
determined by their physical organisation; their consciousness is determined in
just the same way.
Marx,
The German Ideology, 49.
The determinist relationship
between the economic base and social superstructure, known as Historical Materialism,
is first described in The German Ideology.[8] Historic materialism contends that the
catalyst behind societal evolution is materially determined, being predicated
on contradictions between the forces and means of production. As “it is not consciousness that determines
life, but life that determines consciousness”[9],
law is a reflection of the economic base, rather than the reserve as liberals
such as Dworkin would propose.
Under increasing
industrialisation Marx foresaw crystallisation of society into two
classes; bourgeoisie and
proletariat. These relations of
production developed due to particular forces of production under the
capitalist mode of production that coerced the bourgeoisie to extract surplus
value as profit from the proletariat.
Laws, as Marx detailed in Capital,
as one element of the social superstructure, assisted in forcing down wages.[10]
Collins characterises two Marxist
approaches; crude materialism, in which law is simply a reflection of the
economic base; and secondly, class instrumentalism; in which rules emerge
because the ruling class want them to.[11] This distinction continues as an area of
debate, as demonstrated by O'Malley’s attacks of Quinney and Chambliss’ crude
materialist claim that law is a direct tool of powerful classes or groups,
favouring the more interactionist, and less conflict premised theory of
legislative change.[12] The Relative Autonomy Thesis is such a
theory. Contemporary Marxists such as
Marcuse, suggest mechanisms analogous to the Factory Acts and Vagrancy
Acts remain instruments of the ruling class perpetuating conditions
reinforcing this arrangement, especially in relation to the alienating nature
of modern technological rationality.[13]
Base and Superstructure in the
Capitalist Mode of Production
Much of our law, such as
Contract, Property and Commercial Law, is predicated on the existence of the
capitalist mode of production. As Marx’s
major project was the critique of capitalism, irrespective of a belief in
revolution, Marxism has a great deal to notify us of in our contemporary
jurisprudence. Marxism postulates that
in the social production of their existence, people, independent of their will,
enter into definite relations of production appropriate to a given stage in the
development of the materials forces of production.[14] Consequently the societal superstructure,
including but not dominated by law, amongst other hegemonic devices, is
determined by the economic base and the organisation of power in society.[15] Marxist jurisprudence concentrates on the
relationship between law and particular historical, social and economic
structures, seeing law, unlike liberal theory, as having no legitimate
primacy. Frequently encountered legal
rules and doctrine, argue Gramsci[16]
and Althusser[17],
establish modern liberal jurisprudential hegemony.[18]
Scientific Socialism
Marxist epistemology, with
dialectic materialism as the centrepiece of Marxism’s scientific claim,
proclaims in real life, where speculation ends, positive science; the
representation of the practical activity, of the practical progress of
development of men, begins.[19] Whilst Marx’s materialism does not refer to
the assumption of a logically argued ontological position, Marx adopts an
undoubtedly Realist position, in which ideas are the product of the human brain
in sensory transaction with a knowable material world.[20]
These claims contrast with those
of natural lawyers such as Aquinas who believe religion should normatively
guide law; those desiring utilitarian tendencies such as Austin and Bentham; or
objective consistency as some positivists such as Hart, or perhaps integrity,
as perhaps only Dworkin can fully endorse.
Nevertheless, whilst debate as to the scientific credentials of Marxism
continue, Collins claims Marxism’s desire for class reductionism to explain the
dynamic interaction between man and nature risks misconstruing the diversity of
social phenomena in order to confirm the ‘rigid systemic framework of
historical materialism’.[21]
Law and the Dictatorship of the
Proletariat
Law, morality, religion, are to him so many
bourgeois prejudices, behind which lurk in ambush as many bourgeois interests.
Karl
Marx, The Communist Manifesto, 18
Marxism saw development of the
relations of production dialectically, as both inevitable, and creating
hostility. Accelerated by increased
class consciousness, as the contradictions of capitalism perforate the
bourgeois hegemony, inevitable revolution and a dictatorship of the proletariat
would facilitate “socialised production upon a predetermined plan.”[22] Given the scientific nature of Historic
Materialism, and upon recognising the role the state and its laws supply, the proletariat will seize political power
and turn the means of production into state property[23],
then according to Marxist jurisprudence, “As soon as there is no longer any
class to be held in subjection; as soon as class rule and the individual
struggle for existence … are removed, nothing more remains to be repressed.”[24]
Communism and the End of Law
The meaning of history, that
man’s destiny lies in creation of a Communist society where “law will wither
away”[25]
, as men experience a higher stage of being amounting to the realisation of
true freedom, will after transition through Socialism, be achieved.
Justice and Rights
Communism abolishes eternal truths, it
abolishes all religion, and all morality, instead of constituting them on a new
basis.
Karl
Marx, The Communist Manifesto, 24
Marxism argues there is no
absolute concept of justice, justice being dependent on the requirements of a
given mode of production.[26] Lukes claims Marx believes justice, “Does not
provide a set of independent rational standards by which to measure social
relations, but must itself always in turn be explained as arising from and
controlling those relations”.[27]
Marxism believes that rights are
simply a bourgeois creation, and that justice is something only the rich can
achieve in capitalist modes of production.
Anatole France (1894) encapsulated this distinction between formal and
substantive justice as entitlement, drawing attention to “the majestic
egalitarianism of the law, which forbids rich and poor alike to sleep under
bridges, to beg in the streets and to steal bread.”[28] Formal justice as entitlement therefore
allows equal opportunity to the individual without any reference to the unequal
ability to use it, with rights only being anti-socialist if individuals are
taken to be “inherently and irredeemably self-interested.”[29]
Marxist dispute over how rights
and justice will operate in practice are answered by the materialist
proposition that the “distribution of burdens and benefits should not be taken
in accordance with a book of rules, but in the light of the objectives of
social policy.”[30] Campbell distinguishes between Socialist and
Bourgeois Rights, arguing that an interest based theory of rights, rather than
the contract based notions such as Pashukanis’ incorporated in his commodity
exchange theory of law[31],
allow protection of the individual[32],
thereby negating the logical connection between rights and justice.[33]
In Summary
Marxist jurisprudence and Marxist
critiques of law provide invaluable challenges to our thinking as people under
law in a liberal democratic society.
This essay is only the briefest of introductions in a field rich with
reflections concerning the assumptions we construct into our law. Whether you accept the claims of its
doctrine, its influence on shaping the society we live in is more significant
than most of us realise.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Althusser, L.,
1977, For Marx, London: New Left
Books.
Balbus, I., 1978,
‘Commodity Form and Legal Form’ in Reasons, C., The Sociology of Law, Toronto: Butterworths.
Baradat, L., 1991, Political Ideologies: Their Origins and
Impact, 4th Edn., New Jersey: Prentice Hall.
Barbalet, J.,
1983, Marx's Construction of Social
Theory, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Barry, N., 1989, An Introduction to Modern Political Theory,
2nd Edn., London: Macmillan.
Berger, P. and
Luckmann, T., 1975, The Social
Construction of Reality, Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Blackburn, R.,
(Ed.), 1991, After the Fall: The Failure
of Communism, London: Verso.
Cain, M., and Hunt,
A., 1979, Marx and Engels on Law,
London: Academic Press.
Campbell, T., 1988,
Justice, London: Macmillan.
Campbell, T., 1981,
Seven Theories of Human Nature,
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Campbell, T., 1983,
The Left and Rights, London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Collins, H., 1982, Marxism and Law, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Connell, R., 1977, Ruling Class, Ruling Culture, London:
Cambridge University Press.
Cotterrell, R.,
1989, The Politics of Jurisprudence: A
Critical Introduction to Legal Philosophy, London: Butterworths.
Easton, L and K,
Guddat (Eds.), 1967, Writings of the
Young Marx on Philosophy and Society, New York: Anchor.
Engels,
F., 1954, Socialism: Scientific and
Utopian, Moscow: Progress Press.
Foucault, M., 1979,
Discipline and Punish-The Birth of the
Prison, Middlesex: Penguin.
Frankel, B., 1983, Beyond the State?; Dominant Theories and
Socialist Strategies, London: MacMillan.
Frolov, I.
(ed.), 1980, Dictionary of Philosophy,
Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Fromm, E., 1973,
Marx's Concept of Man, New York: Frederick Ungar Publishing.
Gamble, A., 1987, An Introduction To Modern Social And
Political Thought, Hampshire: Macmillan.
Giddens, A., 1981, Capitalism and Modern Social Theory; An
analysis of the writings of Marx, Durkheim and Weber, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Gramsci, A.,
1971, Selections from the Prison
Notebooks, London: Lawrence and Wishart.
Habermas, J.,
1970, Toward a Rational Society,
London: Heinemann.
Harris, J., 1980, Legal Philosophies, London:
Butterworths.
Kellner, D., 1984, Herbert Marcuse and the Crisis of Marxism,
London: Macmillan.
Luhmann, N., 1982, The Differentiation of Society, New
York: Colombia University Press.
Lukes, S., 1986, Power: A Radical View, London: Oxford
University Press.
Marcuse,
H., 1975, One-Dimensional Man,
Boston: Beacon Press.
Marx, K., 1986,
‘Bloody Legislation against the Expropriated, from the end of the 15th.
Century: Forcing Down Wages by Acts of Parliament’ in Capital, Moscow: Progress Press.
Marx, K., 1986, Capital; A Critique of political Economy,
Vol 1; The Process of Production of Capital, Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Marx, K., 1977, Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of
1844, Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Marx, K.,1975, Early Writings, London: Penguin.
Marx K. and Engels F., 1848, Manifesto of the Communist Party; authorised
English translation from the Marx-Engels Institute, Melbourne:
International Bookshop.
Marx, K., 1989,
‘Preface to A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy’ in Karl Marx and Frederick Engels Selected
Works, Moscow: Progress Press.
Marx, K., and
Engels, F., 1965, The German Ideology,
Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Marx, K., and
Engels, F., 1989, Selected Works,
Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Marx, K., 1902, Wage, Labour and Capital, New York: New
York Labor News Company.
McLellan,
D.,1971, Marx’s Grundisse, London:
Macmillan.
McLellan,
D.,1980, The Thought of Karl Marx,
London: Macmillan.
McMurtry, J.,
1978, The Structure of Marx’s World View,
New Jersey: Princeton University Press.
Offe, C., 1985, Disorganised Capitalism: Contemporary
Transformations of Work and Politics, Cambridge: Polity Press.
Ollman, B.,1976,
Alienation; Marx’s Conception of Man in
Capitalist Society, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
O’Malley, P.,
1980, ‘Theories on Structure Versus Causal Determination’ in Tomasic (Ed.) Legislation and Society in Australia,
Sydney: Allen and Unwin.
Tucker, R.,
(ed.),1972, The Marx-Engels Reader,
New York: Norton.
Wacks, R., 1987, Jurisprudence, London: Blackstone Press.
Warrington, R.,
1983, ‘Pashukanis and the commodity form theory’ in Sugarman, D., Legality, Ideology and the State,
London: Academic Press.
22.6 Rights Without Duties
Hohfeld, a legal philosopher, emphasised the
relationship between rights and duties and also the difference between right
and privilege. Hohfeld emphasised that there cannot be a right without a duty.
Right in one person presupposes a duty in another. The concept of a right
without a duty is meaningless. Likewise he also distinguished between rights
and privileges. A privilege is available on sufferance. It is a discretion
vested in the person granting it. A right is an entitlement. On this analysis
what are commonly called rights to employment, welfare, etc, are not rights. A
right to employment is meaningless because there is no person who is under a
duty to employ. Welfare is not a right. It is a privilege which is given to
certain persons.
Whether one agrees with this analysis or not, it
is undeniable that at the commonsense level a right involves a duty in another
person or institution. As an essential commonsense corollary, it must also
involve an acceptance of that duty by the person who is subject to it. It is
ironic in society today that while more and more people are demanding rights,
fewer and fewer people are concerned about duties, least of all those who are
most vocal in the assertion of rights. Governments, the Human Rights Commission
and many other government agencies provide doubtful leadership in this regard.
They are educating people about their rights and are attempting to make more
and more rights available with no reference to logic and commonsense. But they
seem unconcerned about the need to educate people about duties and the
importance of a sense of responsibility.
A dangerous byproduct of the welfare state and
the growth of government is a profound attitudinal change in society which
makes people demand more and more and contribute less and less. This
transformation of the social psyche has taken place imperceptibly to the point
that it unconsciously pervades the entire society. The preoccupation with
rights (particularly state created social and economic rights) has become an
obsession. Although this is not an intrinsic evil, the pursuit of rights
becomes self defeating when it is unaccompanied by the commitment to duties.
The pressures exercised by interest groups have become the dominant feature of
the modern era. These demands come not only from the poor and the
underprivileged, but also from privileged academic, bureaucratic, social and
business groups. At the same time there is a deafening silence on the question
of individual responsibility.
The interventionist welfare state has become a
super patriarchal entity from which individual members have come to expect
solutions to all problems. Rights are being demanded and duties forgotten.
The Bible emphasises duties and responsibilities
(not rights). The Ten Commandments are duties. Duties have been more important
than rights in the Australian Achievement. The emphasis on rights to the near
exclusion of duties and responsibilities in modern society is a challenge.
There is a grave danger in the push towards legislative recognition of
subjective (so-called) rights in response to the demands of politically
influential pressure groups.
A duty-centred society is preferable to a
right-centred society. If individuals are concerned about their duties,
responsibilities and obligations, they cannot but be concerned about the rights
and freedoms of others. A right-centred society is one in which individuals
assert their rights. They are encouraged by the Human Rights Commission and
like Commonwealth and State bodies, to demand rights, with no consideration for
the effect of those demands on other people, eg the right to protest and
demonstrate conflicts with the right of pedestrians and motorists to use the
public roads for the purpose for which roads are built.
Governments and pressure groups which focus on
rights, give no thought to how rights can operate in the absence of a climate
in which the importance of duties is emphasised.
There is no end to the so-called rights which can
be demanded. A right-conscious society, in effect, recognises a few rights and
neglects many others. The rights that are recognised are those which are
demanded by the powerful, the aggressive and the nasty.
There cannot be a right without a duty. An
endless cacophony of demands by interest groups for rights has become a
dominant feature of the modern Australian State (fed by legislation which
encourages these demands). At the same time there is a deafening silence on the
question of individual responsibility. The time has come to realise and to
emphasise that rights, whether material or political, depend on the discharge
of duties. Wealth and prosperity are created by effort. Only continuing effort
can sustain them. Western societies through effort have achieved a level of
prosperity unparalleled in history.
History has continually demonstrated that the
greatest of civilisations decline and fall when they succumb to indulgence at
the expense of discipline and endeavour. The fate of Egyptian and Roman
civilisations are prime examples. It is not too early for Western Civilization
to heed the supreme lesson of human experience.
Analysis of Hohfeldian Conception of Liberty
LI Jian
The conception of right is
fundamental in realms of political, moral and legal philosophy. Although it is
widely used, what is a right or what is the meaning of right is a problem which
needs to be carefully dealt with. There is no doubt that an appropriate
starting point to talk about rights is the remarkable analysis of legal rights in
Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld¡¯s Fundamental Legal Conceptions. Hohfeld distinguished
the conception of right into four sub-conceptions (which are right or claim,
privilege or liberty, power and immunity), and defined them through their
correlatives (i.e. duty, no-right or no-claim, liability, disability or
no-power). In this way, he provided a useful method to turn the general,
ambiguous notion of right into several distinctive, well-defined ideas. Many
authors are inclined to reformulate Hohfeld¡¯s definitions and take them as
their basis to investigate theories of rights.
The
subject of the essay will be focused on the Hohfeldian conception of
liberty-right (or privilege, in his own terminology). Liberty is very important
and essential among various types of rights. It can hardly be imagined that we
could have any rights if we were deprived of our liberty. Hohfeld¡¯s analysis
of liberty could be seen as a theory of the definition of liberty, which is put
forward to clarify the inner structure of liberty. That is, a liberty is
defined by, or is equivalent to a no-right that has an opposite content. As
duty also has certain logical relation to liberty, the other way to put the
definition is that a liberty is merely the negation of the duty with opposite
content. I would like to show that this definition is not manifestly true as it
seems to be at the first sight. Hohfeld does not justify it. Some philosophers
adopt this definition and develop a concept of half-liberty on the basis of it.
Many philosophers take this definition as the only possible explanation of
liberty in the Hohfeldian conceptual structure. I don¡¯t think there is
sufficient reason to do so. In fact, there is a different analysis of liberty
that well conform to our intuition of liberty as free choice without
contradiction to the specified logical relations between Hohfeld¡¯s conceptions
of rights and their correlatives. And it at least shows that the Hohfeldian
definition is unfounded and by no means exclusive one. But before I defend the
intuitive notion of liberty, it would be better to discuss and make clear the
scheme of correlatives and opposites which gives us almost all the analytic
instruments to clarify the ¡°fundamental legal conceptions¡±.
Scheme of Correlatives and Opposites
The main achievement of
Hohfeld¡¯s exploration to the nature of rights is his scheme of ¡°jural
correlatives¡± and ¡°jural opposites¡±.[34][1] For him, all the essence and interrelations of fundamental legal
conceptions consist in the scheme. In consideration of the liberty-debate, I
would confine myself to the part containing only first-order conceptions.[35][2] As indicated in the scheme, a claim is the invariable correlative of a
duty and the invariable opposite of a no-claim; a liberty is the correlative of
a no-claim and the opposite of a duty. What does Hohfeld mean by terms like
¡°correlative¡± and ¡°opposite¡±? He says,
If X has a right against Y
that he shall stay off the former¡¯s land, the correlative (and equivalent) is
that Y is under a duty toward X to stay off the place.[36][3]
Right (or claim) and duty both
indicate relations between two definite persons. A right can be said to
represent a relation between X and Y that Y should stay off X¡¯s land. And a
duty also represents a relation that Y should stay off X¡¯s land. The relations
represented by a right and by its correlative duty are the same. That¡¯s the
reason why Hohfeld takes one conception and its correlative as logically
equivalent to each other. As he claims, when talking about John Austin¡¯s particular
use of the term ¡°right¡±, that
Such a delimitation of
¡°right¡± clearly excludes ¡°legal privilege¡±; for the correlative of the
latter, or ¡°the same notion¡± from a ¡°different aspect¡±, is, of course,
¡°no-right¡± or ¡°no-claim¡±.[37][4]
Like John Austin, Hohfeld
believes that all fundamental conceptions indicate nothing but certain jural
relations.[38][5] And from different point of views, one relation could always be
regarded as two different conceptions. From X¡¯s point of view, the relation
that Y shall stay off X¡¯s land is a right residing in X; from Y¡¯s point of
view, the same relation is a duty on Y. A relation connects a right on one
person and a duty on another. Thus a right implies a duty representing the same
certain relation, and vice versa. Thereby these two conceptions are correlative
or logically equivalent to each other. But a right is not by all means
correlative to any duty. X¡¯s right that Y shall not enter on X¡¯s land
unquestionably is not correlative to Y¡¯s duty that he shall not cause harm to
X. The right and duty that correlative to each other must be representing the
relation constitute by them. Hohfeld calls his scheme of conceptions as scheme
of relations. A right always relates to a duty, a liberty to a no-right, etc. I
think this is the only foundation that a right can be taken as equivalent to a
duty. Besides this, how could Hohfeld find any reason to justify the idea of
¡°invariable correlative¡± or logical equivalent? It could not be justified
just by observing the way people use the terms right and duty, especially when
there are many cases of confused or loose or even proliferated use of these
terms. If this is true, it is essential to all analyses of Hohfeldian
conceptions, because it is on the idea of relation that all the logical
connections of Hohfeldian conceptions are founded. Opposites are conceptions
representing two relations that negate each other. That is why the opposite of
a right is a no-right; and the opposite of a liberty is of course duty, since liberty
is equivalent to no-right and duty equivalent to right.
Although
many commentators agree that Hohfeldian conceptions are relational, it is not
very clear what relational means. L. W. Sumner holds that ¡°all of Hohfeld¡¯s
conceptions are relations between two distinct parties.¡±[39][6] For Hohfeld, two parties are two determinate persons in whom the right
and the duty reside. But relation is also construed as between ¡°a person and
an object¡±, as Joseph Raz maintains.[40][7] What he has in mind is rights in rem. He stresses that a holder of the
right of that kind certainly has a relation to an object. I think the point is
that relation does not mean any kind of connection. If someone has a right to a
tangible property, it does not follow that he has a legal relation in the
Hohfeldian sense. This is just because a property cannot be the holder of
rights or bearer of duties. For instance, I have a right to my computer, but it
doesn¡¯t mean that my computer has a duty to me to be used by me. If someone else
shall not dominate the use of my computer, it doesn¡¯t imply that my computer
has any liberty or immunity to other people. The bearer of rights or their
correlatives can only be entities that can perform or refrain actions.
Ultimately, the relation means a relation between a right and a duty, not
necessarily requiring two distinctive parties. If I have a right to myself that
I shall live a virtuous life, then I myself have a duty to live such a life. I
don¡¯t see any reason that one particular party cannot be the right-holder and
duty-bearer at the same time.
Hohfeld
makes two assertions with respect to the relation thought of conceptions. One
is that the relations are between a right-holder and a duty-bearer. Another is
that only particular or definite person can be right-holder or duty-bearer.
These two assertions are quite distinct from each other that one can accept the
first and reject the second. Communities constituted by people, countries and
some other organizations can also be holders of rights and bearers of duties.
When we say that one country should not invade another country, no doubt that
we are taking countries as duty-bears and right-holders. And there is no
problem that one party would be collective and the other single person. All
these entities as parties in which rights or duties reside won¡¯t affect the
whole scheme of Hohfeldian conceptions and its inner structure. Concerning the
first assertion, counterexamples can also be proposed. For example, a right in
rem or a right to an object is non-relational. That means a right to an object
has no correlative duty on any other parties, though other peripheral rights
against other parties may always protect it.[41][8] It seems that the first assertion should be rejected too. But if we
confine our debate to relational right-conceptions, then the Hohfeldian scheme
and Hohfeldian analysis are still very useful. No doubt many rights and
liberties are relational, and for these rights and liberties, Hohfeld reveals
the correlatives to them. Although his believe that every conception is
relational in nature is not correct, his scheme might be well applicable to
every relational conceptions. In fact, I think the relational view is the
foundation upon which the whole Hohfeldian conceptual structure is established.
And I would like to regard the scheme of conceptions as the background to
discuss in which way the relational liberty shall be defined.
How to define liberty
Among the first-order
conceptions, the pair of right and duty has comparatively clear meaning. There
are positive rights, i.e. rights with positive content, such as an employer¡¯s
right against his employee that the latter should work for him. There are also
negative rights, rights with negative content, such as one person¡¯s right that
another one should not enter on his land. In any of these cases, the content of
a duty is the same with that of a right. But when analyzing the notion of
liberty, there is some distinctive difference in Hohfeld¡¯s mind. He says,
¡whereas X has a right or claim
that Y, the other man, should stay off the land, he himself has the privilege
of entering on the land; or, in equivalent words, X does not have a duty to
stay off. The privilege of entering is the negation of a duty to stay off.
Thus, the correlative of X¡¯s
right that Y shall not enter on the land is Y¡¯s duty not to enter; but the
correlative of X¡¯s privilege of entering himself is manifestly Y¡¯s
¡°no-right¡± that X shall not enter.[42][9]
The biggest difference between
definitions of right and liberty seems to be that the content of a liberty is
exactly opposite to that of its correlative. But what exactly is the content or
tenor of a liberty? Since liberty is a relational conception, its content must
mean a relation¡¯s content, and this relation is represented by the liberty. As
has been shown, one relation is designated both by one conception and by its
correlative. Therefore the correlative to the liberty, i.e. no-right, also
takes the content of the relation to be its own content. That is to say, the
content of a liberty must be the same as the content of a no-right. But why
does Hohfeld regulate that the content of a no-right is contrary to that of a
liberty? Hohfeld himself does not define liberty through its correlative as he
does with regard to right. He gives the definition as ¡°¡the mere negation of
a duty¡having a content of tenor precisely opposite to that of the privilege
in question.¡±[43][10] It seems to be his strong intuition that a liberty to do something is
undoubtedly equivalent to a duty not to do that. But intuition is just
intuition. How could his definition be justified without resorting to the
relational essence of conceptions? If he does so, how could he demonstrate that
a liberty to do and a no-right not to do represent and constitute the same
relation? And what is the content of the relation£¿I don¡¯t think these are
questions that can be slightly overlooked. For a liberty to do defined as the
negation of a duty not to do is, in Hohfeld¡¯s view, consistent with a duty to
do. That means one may have a liberty and a duty at the same time.
Thus, if, for some special
reason, X has contracted with Y to go on the former¡¯s own land, it is obvious
that X has, as regards Y, both the privilege of entering and the duty of
entering.[44][11]
One can be both at liberty to do
something and obligated to do that. This is rather contrary to our normal
intuition that liberty is free choice without any restriction. So, an intuition
seems to be reasonable leads to a conclusion contradictory to our more common
intuition.
Since liberty and duty are opposites, i.e. logical contradictories, the
former could be defined by the negation of the latter. This seems to be out of
question, and being at liberty normally refers to the state lacking duty. But
the way that Hohfeld uses the negation of duty to define liberty is not
unquestionable. If the right/duty relation and the relation represented by
liberty negate each other, then liberty could be well defined just by the
negation of duty, or by the lacking of duty. Why should we define liberty as
negation of duty with opposite content? In order to define liberty, the
negation of duty is adequate; but Hohfeld also negates the content of the duty,
therefore he actually negates the duty twice. I call it double negation. If we
only negate once, all the logical connections between Hohfeldian conceptions
still remain. There is no need to negate a given duty twice.
The content of right or duty is directional.[45][12] The content is either to do something or not to do something; that is
the quality of restriction, whereas the content of liberty could be construed
as negation of the directionality of a given duty. Negation of directionality
means free choice between two opposite directional actions, and that is the
essence of liberty. In which sense a liberty/no-right relation negates a
right/duty relation? I think it is the annulment of the directionality of the
latter. In this way, liberty is in essence non-directionality, opposite to duty
or right, no matter what specific direction the duty or right has. Such a
liberty is a liberty to do or not to do something. But ordinarily, we would
often say a liberty to do something or a liberty not to do something. That may
represent certain action that we prefer to choose, not necessarily the real
logical quality of the liberty. Given a liberty to do something, if I choose
not to do that, it would not violate anyone¡¯s right, since no one has a right
that I shall do that. The liberty to do something implies the liberty not to do
it, and vice versa. The content of a liberty could also be said to be certain
action, just like the content of duty or right. But liberty ensures the free
option on the subject; whether he chooses to do or forbears to do, there is no
restriction on his choice. In other words, there is no directionality upon this
certain action.
Sumner displays ¡°the logical connections among first-order Hohfeldian
normative relations. Where X and Y are persons and V is some act, the rows in
the following matrix give correlatives and the columns (and diagonals) give
opposites.
X has a
liberty with Y has no
claim against X
respect to
Y to V that X not V
X has a
duty to Y Y has a claim
against X
It is possible for a liberty
defined as free choice to be accommodated in such a diagram, and all logical
connections of correlatives and opposites are unchanged. The alternative
diagram is as follows,
X has a
liberty with respect Y has no
claim against X
to Y V or
not V that X V or not V
X has a
duty to Y V or Y has a claim
against X that X V or
X has a
duty to Y not to V Y has a claim
against X that X not V
Where X has a liberty to V or
not to V, Y has neither a claim that X V nor a claim that X not V. Here a
no-claim that X V plus a no-claim that X not V is abbreviated to a no-claim
that X V or not V. X¡¯s liberty to or not to V indicates his control over this
action, whether he V or not V is independent of Y¡¯s control or claim. The
opposite to X¡¯s liberty could be either X¡¯s duty to V or X¡¯s duty not to V.
Where X has liberty with regard to V, he has no duty at all. A duty with any
kind of content, negative or positive, would be contradictory to a liberty. In
this table, the conception of liberty is still correlative to no-claim and
opposite of duty. In spite of the new characterization of liberty, the
connections and relational qualities of first-order conceptions are retained.
It at least shows that Hohfeld¡¯s definition of liberty can be separated from
his scheme of logical connections of conceptions. We can apply this scheme to
right-analysis and insist a different notion of liberty at the same time. I have
argued that Hohfeld¡¯s definition is unfounded or unjustified; even if there is
adequate reason to accept his view, I hold that an alternative definition is
feasible as well.
Why Hohfeld advocates liberty as being compatible with duty? When he
takes liberty into consideration, it seems that he has been influenced by the
directionality of right and duty. Duty and right must be directional; to say a
duty to do or not to do something is nothing but nonsense. It may appear to him
that liberty should be directional too. Manifestly a liberty to do is
contradictory to a duty not to do; this ostensible connection might be taken as
definition of liberty. Besides, if liberty were construed as free choice, then
not only a duty not to do, but also a duty to do would be contradictories to
such a liberty. Then the single connection between liberty and duty might be
lost. Perhaps this definition of liberty on the basis of duty comes from
Hohfeld¡¯s view that right/duty relation is the strictest one among all fundamental
relations.[47][14] Therefore, when analyzing liberty, the contents that right and duty
have and the way in which they are defined might affect Hohfeld. He defines
liberty through a directional duty and then makes liberty directional too. The
problem is why right/duty should be regarded as the relation in the strictest
sense, why right or claim is stricter than liberty and other right-conceptions.
Hohfeld himself doesn¡¯t provide any reason. The truth is that liberty is not
less important than claim from both legal and moral point of view. We would say
that one is deprived of his basic right if he could not enjoy unencumbered
choice or act freely. For claim-right describes the way that other people
should or should not do, it alone cannot capture the core notion of legal and
moral rights. Only liberty ensures one¡¯s control over his action. The idea of
personal control over one¡¯s action is the main idea belonging to liberty.
Generally it runs counter to control or claim from others, which is equivalent
to the person¡¯s duty. To take liberty as strict and fundamental as
claim-right, first we would confirm the common idea of liberty as free choice.
And it¡¯s correlative is other person¡¯s no-claim that the liberty-holder shall
V or not V. Secondly, the opposite relation, i.e. right/duty relation would be
defined on the basis of this idea of liberty. The lacking of liberty or the
negation of liberty is of course duty to others, no matter what content the
duty has. Both a duty V and a duty not V are opposite to a liberty V or not V.
Thus, upon this idea of liberty, a whole scheme of first-order conceptions can
also be developed. There is nothing lost, but the general idea captured. Maybe
Hohfeld values symmetries of the scheme, and to some extent, a liberty opposite
to both positive and negative duties may seem to lack symmetry. Even if it is
true, it cannot deny the legitimate analysis and definition of liberty as free
choice.
Fallacy of half liberty
Sumner accepts Hohfeld¡¯s
definition of liberty and calls it half liberty. He writes,
Suppose that I have no duty
either to attend the meeting or not to do so. I thus have two logically
distinct Hohfeldian liberties. Call each of these a half liberty and their
conjunction a full liberty. Then I have a half liberty to attend the meeting, a
half liberty not to attend it, and a full liberty to attend it or not. In
general I have a full liberty with respect to anything which I am neither
obligated to do nor obligated not to do. Unlike half liberties, full liberties
ensure a normatively unencumbered choice between options.[48][15]
A liberty to do is merely
equivalent to the negation of the duty not to do. Such a liberty just ensures
the liberty-holder¡¯s doing something; do not ensure his not doing something.
If I haven¡¯t a duty not to do, I may just have a liberty to do, not a liberty
to do or not to do. That¡¯s why Sumner calls it half liberty, for a liberty to
do and a liberty not to do may not exist at the same time. And he regards these
two half liberties as conjuncts of a full liberty. Then a full liberty is
equivalent to the negation of the duty to do plus the negation of the duty not
to do. But the fact is that we don¡¯t need to negate two duties to have a full
liberty. In order to enjoy a full liberty, to negate one duty is enough. If I
have a duty to do, then I don¡¯t have a duty not to do. It is impossible to be
obligated to do and not to do the same thing. These two duties, therefore,
cannot exist at the same time. Then if my duty not to do is negated or removed,
then I must have a liberty to do; but as I still do not have a duty to do, I
also have a liberty not to do. Thus I get a full liberty through the negation
of a duty not to do. This shows that a full liberty is opposite to one
determinate duty; the equivalent to the negation of such a duty is not a half
liberty, but a full liberty. The logical connections between liberty and duty
are not what Sumner thinks.
Let us suppose that the conception of half liberty is feasible. In the
case that I have a duty to do, negation of the duty leads to a full liberty.
That demonstrates that the negation of a duty to do, is not in fact equivalent
to a half liberty not to do. A similar conclusion can be drawn in the case of a
negative duty. The conception full liberty is certainly the opposite of a duty.
If it is reasonable that full liberty and half liberty are distinctive from
each other, then both of them are all opposites of a certain duty. Some
philosophers accept the equivalence of the negation of duty and half liberty.
As Rowan gives us,
¡°Specifically, X is said to
have a privilege to perform a certain act if and only if X has no duty to
refrain from performing that act.¡±[49][16]
The same thing is expressed in
another way by John Finnis,
¡°B has a liberty (relative to
A) to ¦Ã•, if and only if A has no-claim-right (¡®a no-right¡¯) that B should
not¦Ã•.¡±[50][17]
It seems that the regulation of liberty as half
liberty at least needs to be modified because of the connection between full
liberty and duty. The point is, if full liberty is also opposite of a certain
duty, positive or negative, and if we give up the above definition of half
liberty, then in which way we can define half liberty and how to show the
logical distinctiveness of this concept. As full liberty can be well justified
to be equivalent to the negation of a certain duty, there is no need and no
sufficient reason to hold the idea of half liberty. In fact, such an idea is
not only groundless but also redundant. Besides, as has been shown above, a
duty to do implies a liberty to do, because a duty to do implies the lack of a
duty not to do and the latter means a liberty to do. If this is true, under any
circumstances people will always hold liberty. One will be at liberty to do
what he is obligated to; and of course he will also be at liberty if he is not
under obligation. It seems to be absurd that liberty exists everywhere. In
general, we take liberty as an advantage, as an opposite of obligation that is
disadvantage. But the idea of half liberty implied by duty destroys the
distinction between liberty and obligation. And how could we make clear the
notion of obligation? If we negate a half liberty to do, we will get a half
liberty not to do, and vice versa; if we negate a full liberty, we will get a
disjunction of two half liberties. Generally speaking, we will not be able to
negate liberty.
Sumner thinks that ¡° this feature of liberties follows from the fact
that they are simply deontic permissions¡±, I am at liberty to do whatever the
rules permit me to do.[51][18] But if I am permitted both to do and not to do a thing, I still do not
have liberty in the sense that I myself have control over my action. Full
liberty cannot be identified with liberty in common sense as free choice. It
seems to him that one of the main reasons to maintain the conception of half
liberty is that there are mandatory rights, which are burdens as well as
benefits.[52][19] He gives the instance of children¡¯s right and duty to attend school.
Such right may be regarded as claim-right, not liberty-right. As a claim, it is
certainly compatible with duty. For only a no-claim can be the opposite of the
same subject¡¯s claim-right. Similarly, my right to chair the meeting may
co-exist with my duty to do so, if the right is regarded as a power to chair
the meeting. Because I may have a power and a duty at the same time, these two
relations do not contradict each other. In all these cases, the so-called
mandatory rights are not liberty-rights. We should be careful to deal with such
rights. As Hohfeld endeavors to distinguish different conceptions of rights, it
is of course necessary to make clear which right can be taken as liberty in the
Hohfeldian sense. And even if a few instances of mandatory liberty can be
found, I doubt whether they can support the reasonability of this concept.
Since so many liberties are treasured as free choice and so many burdens cannot
be looked upon as benefits, liberty-right as relational conception in
Hohfeldian scheme should be construed as free choice. The definition Hohfeld
himself gives concerning this concept may be just an arbitrary thesis that he
has made.
Bibliography
Carter, Alan. (1989) The
Philosophical Foundations of Property Rights.
Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Feinberg, Joel. (1973) Social Philosophy.
Prentice-Hall, Inc.
Finnis, John. (1980) Natural Law and Natural
Rights. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Gewirth, Alan. (1978) Reason and Morality. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Hart, H. L. A. (1982) Essays on Bentham: Studies in
Jurisprudence and Political Theory. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
©¤ (1983) Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy.
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Hohfeld, Wesley Newcomb. (1923) Fundamental Legal
Conceptions As Applied in Judicial Reasoning (Walter Wheeler Cook, ed.) New
Haven: Yale University Press.
Lyons, David. (1994) Rights, Welfare and Mill¡¯s
Moral Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Raz, Joseph. (1980) The Concept of A Legal System:
An Introduction to the Theory of Legal System. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Rowan, John R. (1999) Conflicts of Rights: Moral
Theory and Social Policy Implications. Westview Press.
Simmons, A. John. (1992) The Lockean Theory of
Rights. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Sumner, L. W. (1987) The Moral Foundation of
Rights. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Tapper, C. F. H. (1973) ¡°Powers and Secondary
Rules of Change,¡± in Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence (second series), A. W. B.
Simpson, ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Balancing Rights,
Duties, and Underlying Values
In their reluctance to unconditionally embrace rights language and logic, some participants turned to the concepts of duty and responsibility, which are commonly believed to be deeply embedded in East Asian cultures. In the case of the antinuclear movement in Taiwan, the right to a clean environment might be redefined as a duty to protect land from those claiming a right to do what they want with it. In relation to the issue of justice between generations, Emmerson raised doubts over "imputing an abstract right of our devising to individuals who do not yet exist, instead of assuming responsibility today for future generations." Likewise, the relationship of rights to duties came up in the paper on Thai prostitution. Again, Emmerson asked whether "alongside the sex worker's rights, her and her clients responsibilities, to each other and to themselves, should also be taken into account."
Individual rights and collective duties are often di-chotomized and
manipulated in the discourse on human rights in the region. But, there can be
no viable notion of a right without a corresponding notion of responsibility
and vice versa. Yasuaki Onuma of the University of Tokyo criticized the
simplistic abandonment of rights and resort to the "opposite" notion
of duty. Onuma argued that in both Eastern and Western traditions the concept
of an individual exists, but "not in an isolated manner." Rather, the
individual "coexists with a concept of collectivity." Arguing that
"dichotomized rights and duties as well as individuals and collectives are
the same modern construct," he maintained that the exclusive emphasis
placed on responsibility and duty by many Asian or African leaders is
wrong-headed. In their reluctance to unconditionally embrace rights language and logic, some participants turned to the concepts of duty and responsibility, which are commonly believed to be deeply embedded in East Asian cultures. In the case of the antinuclear movement in Taiwan, the right to a clean environment might be redefined as a duty to protect land from those claiming a right to do what they want with it. In relation to the issue of justice between generations, Emmerson raised doubts over "imputing an abstract right of our devising to individuals who do not yet exist, instead of assuming responsibility today for future generations." Likewise, the relationship of rights to duties came up in the paper on Thai prostitution. Again, Emmerson asked whether "alongside the sex worker's rights, her and her clients responsibilities, to each other and to themselves, should also be taken into account."
In his paper on the right to political participation in China Xia Yong of the Chinese Academy of Social Sciences portrays rights and duties in a different light, as fluid concepts and part of a continuum. Describing the transformation of the traditional notion of "sacred duty" into individual right, Xia Yong writes that in ancient China,
there was not any legitimacy for
seeking individual interests and advantage by taking part in public affairs....
Political participation was a sacred individual duty to be fulfilled for the
people, for the country, and for self-realization, rather than a right.
Until the introduction of rights language from the West, "the idea of
collective rights overshadowed and, in many cases, replaced individual rights,
creating a correlative individual duty." Duty-bearers were regarded as
shareholders of collective rights. This concept of a sacred duty has since been
used to legitimize the contemporary Chinese regime. As a result,
"participation has become a no-choice-duty rather than a chosen
duty." Daniel Bell of the University of Hong Kong warned that given present realities in China, the writings of ancient Confucian sages may have little bearing on con-temporary Chinese attitudes toward political partici-pation. Bell added that an interest in public affairs, with a certain degree of commitment to the common good, will evolve once ordinary Chinese "feel they can make a difference." Whether this interest will manifest itself as a right to democratic participation or as a duty within an increasingly democratic society has yet to be seen.
Participants suggested moving beyond the binary concept of rights and duties to examine the values that sustain and give them meaning in a given society. Onuma suggested a reconsideration of "notions of virtue, prudence, consideration, and thoughtfulness," while Chandra Muzzafar of Just World Trust in Malaysia emphasized the values of "justice, compassion, restraint, and spiritual balance." The pursuit of individual rights, said Muzzafar, will "erode the very values needed to sustain them in the long run." The human righs discourse may need to develop a holistic understanding of the individual, the family, and the community, and the explicit values that can invigorate not only rights and responsibilities, but also roles and relationships.
© 2004 Carnegie Council on Ethics and International Affairs.
No material on this site may be used in part or in whole by any other
publication or website without the written permission of the Carnegie Council.
Marxist
Jurisprudence
Tutor:
Chris Behrens
Student:
David Risstrom: 9106105
In the social production of their existence,
men inevitably enter into definite relations, which are independent of their
will, namely relations of production appropriate to a given stage in the
development of their material forces of production. The totality of these relations constitute
the economic structure of society, the real foundation, on which arises a legal
and political superstructure and to which correspond definite forms of social
consciousness.
Karl
Marx, Preface to A Contribution to the
Critique of Political Economy, 521.[53]
Marxist jurisprudence posits that
legal relations are determined by the economic base of particular kinds of
society and modes of production.[54] Marxist thought’s primary focus rests on
political economy and the corresponding power relations within society,
providing the most extensive critique to date of liberal tradition on which
many of our legal presuppositions are founded.
To this end, this essay examines law, its structure, motivation and
consequences for justice and rights from a Marxian jurisprudential perspective.
Marxism and Law
Your ideas are but the outgrowth of the conditions
of your bourgeois production and bourgeois property, just as your jurisprudence
is but the will of your class made into a law for all, a will, whose essential
character and direction are determined by the economical conditions of
existence in your class.
Karl
Marx, The Communist Manifesto, 24.
Law is not of central concern to
Marxists jurisprudentialists, as law in the capitalist mode of production is
seen as an instrument of class oppression perpetuated as a consequence of its
particular historical, social and economic structures. Indeed, wishing to avoid liberal
predisposition towards legal fetishism, Marxists deny the degree of importance
jurisprudence typically affords law in analyses of the composition and
determination of social formations.[55]
What is Marxism?
Marxist theories of political
economy, expounded upon the notions of Karl Marx (1818-83) and Friedrich Engels
(1820-95), consider law an instrument of class oppression that benefits the
ruling class through oppression of the proletariat. The common law system of criminal and civil
law, which protects personal and private property rights, as well as facilitating
predicability in social life, is regarded as “no more than a system of coercion
designed to protect bourgeois ownership of the means of production”.[56]
Yet, despite Marx and Engels’
failure to develop a systematic approach to law[57],
and claims of failure in Eastern Europe and the Soviet Union, Marxism’s
materialist emphasis, particularly concerning the notion of alienation and its
consequences as outlined by Ollman[58],
assists its contemporary paucity.[59]
Historical Materialism
Men have history because they must produce
their life, and because they must produce it moreover in a certain way: this is
determined by their physical organisation; their consciousness is determined in
just the same way.
Marx,
The German Ideology, 49.
The determinist relationship
between the economic base and social superstructure, known as Historical
Materialism, is first described in The
German Ideology.[60] Historic materialism contends that the
catalyst behind societal evolution is materially determined, being predicated
on contradictions between the forces and means of production. As “it is not consciousness that determines
life, but life that determines consciousness”[61],
law is a reflection of the economic base, rather than the reserve as liberals
such as Dworkin would propose.
Under increasing
industrialisation Marx foresaw crystallisation of society into two
classes; bourgeoisie and
proletariat. These relations of
production developed due to particular forces of production under the
capitalist mode of production that coerced the bourgeoisie to extract surplus
value as profit from the proletariat.
Laws, as Marx detailed in Capital,
as one element of the social superstructure, assisted in forcing down wages.[62]
Collins characterises two Marxist
approaches; crude materialism, in which law is simply a reflection of the
economic base; and secondly, class instrumentalism; in which rules emerge
because the ruling class want them to.[63] This distinction continues as an area of
debate, as demonstrated by O'Malley’s attacks of Quinney and Chambliss’ crude
materialist claim that law is a direct tool of powerful classes or groups,
favouring the more interactionist, and less conflict premised theory of
legislative change.[64] The Relative Autonomy Thesis is such a
theory. Contemporary Marxists such as
Marcuse, suggest mechanisms analogous to the Factory Acts and Vagrancy
Acts remain instruments of the ruling class perpetuating conditions
reinforcing this arrangement, especially in relation to the alienating nature
of modern technological rationality.[65]
Base and Superstructure in the
Capitalist Mode of Production
Much of our law, such as
Contract, Property and Commercial Law, is predicated on the existence of the
capitalist mode of production. As Marx’s
major project was the critique of capitalism, irrespective of a belief in
revolution, Marxism has a great deal to notify us of in our contemporary
jurisprudence. Marxism postulates that
in the social production of their existence, people, independent of their will,
enter into definite relations of production appropriate to a given stage in the
development of the materials forces of production.[66] Consequently the societal superstructure,
including but not dominated by law, amongst other hegemonic devices, is
determined by the economic base and the organisation of power in society.[67] Marxist jurisprudence concentrates on the
relationship between law and particular historical, social and economic
structures, seeing law, unlike liberal theory, as having no legitimate primacy. Frequently encountered legal rules and
doctrine, argue Gramsci[68]
and Althusser[69],
establish modern liberal jurisprudential hegemony.[70]
Scientific Socialism
Marxist epistemology, with
dialectic materialism as the centrepiece of Marxism’s scientific claim,
proclaims in real life, where speculation ends, positive science; the
representation of the practical activity, of the practical progress of
development of men, begins.[71] Whilst Marx’s materialism does not refer to
the assumption of a logically argued ontological position, Marx adopts an
undoubtedly Realist position, in which ideas are the product of the human brain
in sensory transaction with a knowable material world.[72]
These claims contrast with those
of natural lawyers such as Aquinas who believe religion should normatively
guide law; those desiring utilitarian tendencies such as Austin and Bentham; or
objective consistency as some positivists such as Hart, or perhaps integrity,
as perhaps only Dworkin can fully endorse.
Nevertheless, whilst debate as to the scientific credentials of Marxism
continue, Collins claims Marxism’s desire for class reductionism to explain the
dynamic interaction between man and nature risks misconstruing the diversity of
social phenomena in order to confirm the ‘rigid systemic framework of
historical materialism’.[73]
Law and the Dictatorship of the
Proletariat
Law, morality, religion, are to him so many
bourgeois prejudices, behind which lurk in ambush as many bourgeois interests.
Karl
Marx, The Communist Manifesto, 18
Marxism saw development of the
relations of production dialectically, as both inevitable, and creating
hostility. Accelerated by increased
class consciousness, as the contradictions of capitalism perforate the
bourgeois hegemony, inevitable revolution and a dictatorship of the proletariat
would facilitate “socialised production upon a predetermined plan.”[74] Given the scientific nature of Historic
Materialism, and upon recognising the role the state and its laws supply, the proletariat will seize political power
and turn the means of production into state property[75],
then according to Marxist jurisprudence, “As soon as there is no longer any
class to be held in subjection; as soon as class rule and the individual
struggle for existence … are removed, nothing more remains to be repressed.”[76]
Communism and the End of Law
The meaning of history, that
man’s destiny lies in creation of a Communist society where “law will wither
away”[77]
, as men experience a higher stage of being amounting to the realisation of
true freedom, will after transition through Socialism, be achieved.
Justice and Rights
Communism abolishes eternal truths, it
abolishes all religion, and all morality, instead of constituting them on a new
basis.
Karl
Marx, The Communist Manifesto, 24
Marxism argues there is no
absolute concept of justice, justice being dependent on the requirements of a
given mode of production.[78] Lukes claims Marx believes justice, “Does not
provide a set of independent rational standards by which to measure social
relations, but must itself always in turn be explained as arising from and
controlling those relations”.[79]
Marxism believes that rights are
simply a bourgeois creation, and that justice is something only the rich can
achieve in capitalist modes of production.
Anatole France (1894) encapsulated this distinction between formal and
substantive justice as entitlement, drawing attention to “the majestic
egalitarianism of the law, which forbids rich and poor alike to sleep under
bridges, to beg in the streets and to steal bread.”[80] Formal justice as entitlement therefore
allows equal opportunity to the individual without any reference to the unequal
ability to use it, with rights only being anti-socialist if individuals are
taken to be “inherently and irredeemably self-interested.”[81]
Marxist dispute over how rights
and justice will operate in practice are answered by the materialist
proposition that the “distribution of burdens and benefits should not be taken
in accordance with a book of rules, but in the light of the objectives of
social policy.”[82] Campbell distinguishes between Socialist and
Bourgeois Rights, arguing that an interest based theory of rights, rather than
the contract based notions such as Pashukanis’ incorporated in his commodity
exchange theory of law[83],
allow protection of the individual[84],
thereby negating the logical connection between rights and justice.[85]
In Summary
Marxist jurisprudence and Marxist
critiques of law provide invaluable challenges to our thinking as people under
law in a liberal democratic society.
This essay is only the briefest of introductions in a field rich with
reflections concerning the assumptions we construct into our law. Whether you accept the claims of its
doctrine, its influence on shaping the society we live in is more significant
than most of us realise.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Althusser, L.,
1977, For Marx, London: New Left
Books.
Balbus, I., 1978,
‘Commodity Form and Legal Form’ in Reasons, C., The Sociology of Law, Toronto: Butterworths.
Baradat, L., 1991, Political Ideologies: Their Origins and
Impact, 4th Edn., New Jersey: Prentice Hall.
Barbalet, J.,
1983, Marx's Construction of Social
Theory, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Barry, N., 1989, An Introduction to Modern Political Theory,
2nd Edn., London: Macmillan.
Berger, P. and
Luckmann, T., 1975, The Social
Construction of Reality, Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Blackburn, R.,
(Ed.), 1991, After the Fall: The Failure
of Communism, London: Verso.
Cain, M., and Hunt,
A., 1979, Marx and Engels on Law,
London: Academic Press.
Campbell, T., 1988,
Justice, London: Macmillan.
Campbell, T., 1981,
Seven Theories of Human Nature,
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Campbell, T., 1983,
The Left and Rights, London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Collins, H., 1982, Marxism and Law, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Connell, R., 1977, Ruling Class, Ruling Culture, London:
Cambridge University Press.
Cotterrell, R.,
1989, The Politics of Jurisprudence: A
Critical Introduction to Legal Philosophy, London: Butterworths.
Easton, L and K,
Guddat (Eds.), 1967, Writings of the Young
Marx on Philosophy and Society, New York: Anchor.
Engels,
F., 1954, Socialism: Scientific and
Utopian, Moscow: Progress Press.
Foucault, M., 1979,
Discipline and Punish-The Birth of the
Prison, Middlesex: Penguin.
Frankel, B., 1983, Beyond the State?; Dominant Theories and
Socialist Strategies, London: MacMillan.
Frolov, I.
(ed.), 1980, Dictionary of Philosophy,
Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Fromm, E., 1973,
Marx's Concept of Man, New York: Frederick Ungar Publishing.
Gamble, A., 1987, An Introduction To Modern Social And
Political Thought, Hampshire: Macmillan.
Giddens, A., 1981, Capitalism and Modern Social Theory; An
analysis of the writings of Marx, Durkheim and Weber, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Gramsci, A.,
1971, Selections from the Prison
Notebooks, London: Lawrence and Wishart.
Habermas, J.,
1970, Toward a Rational Society,
London: Heinemann.
Harris, J., 1980, Legal Philosophies, London:
Butterworths.
Kellner, D., 1984, Herbert Marcuse and the Crisis of Marxism,
London: Macmillan.
Luhmann, N., 1982, The Differentiation of Society, New
York: Colombia University Press.
Lukes, S., 1986, Power: A Radical View, London: Oxford
University Press.
Marcuse,
H., 1975, One-Dimensional Man,
Boston: Beacon Press.
Marx, K., 1986,
‘Bloody Legislation against the Expropriated, from the end of the 15th.
Century: Forcing Down Wages by Acts of Parliament’ in Capital, Moscow: Progress Press.
Marx, K., 1986, Capital; A Critique of political Economy,
Vol 1; The Process of Production of Capital, Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Marx, K., 1977, Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of
1844, Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Marx, K.,1975, Early Writings, London: Penguin.
Marx K. and Engels F., 1848, Manifesto of the Communist Party; authorised
English translation from the Marx-Engels Institute, Melbourne:
International Bookshop.
Marx, K., 1989,
‘Preface to A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy’ in Karl Marx and Frederick Engels Selected
Works, Moscow: Progress Press.
Marx, K., and
Engels, F., 1965, The German Ideology,
Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Marx, K., and
Engels, F., 1989, Selected Works,
Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Marx, K., 1902, Wage, Labour and Capital, New York: New
York Labor News Company.
McLellan,
D.,1971, Marx’s Grundisse, London:
Macmillan.
McLellan,
D.,1980, The Thought of Karl Marx,
London: Macmillan.
McMurtry, J.,
1978, The Structure of Marx’s World View,
New Jersey: Princeton University Press.
Offe, C., 1985, Disorganised Capitalism: Contemporary
Transformations of Work and Politics, Cambridge: Polity Press.
Ollman, B.,1976,
Alienation; Marx’s Conception of Man in
Capitalist Society, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
O’Malley, P.,
1980, ‘Theories on Structure Versus Causal Determination’ in Tomasic (Ed.) Legislation and Society in Australia,
Sydney: Allen and Unwin.
Tucker, R.,
(ed.),1972, The Marx-Engels Reader,
New York: Norton.
Wacks, R., 1987, Jurisprudence, London: Blackstone Press.
Warrington, R.,
1983, ‘Pashukanis and the commodity form theory’ in Sugarman, D., Legality, Ideology and the State,
London: Academic Press.
[1] Marx, K., ‘Preface to A Contribution to the
Critique of Political Economy’ in Karl
Marx and Frederick Engels Selected Works, Moscow: Progress Press, 1989 521.
[2] Balbus, I., ‘Commodity Form and
Legal Form’ in Reasons, C., The Sociology
of Law, Toronto:
Butterworths, 1978 83.
[4] Barry, N., An Introduction
to Modern Political Theory, London:
Macmillan, 1989 53.
[5] Cain, M., and Hunt, A., 1979, Marx
and Engels on Law, London:
Academic Press.
[6] Ollman, B.,1976, Alienation;
Marx’s Conception of Man in Capitalist Society, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
[9] Marx, K., The German
Ideology, Moscow:
Progress Publishers, 1976 42.
[10] Marx, K., ‘Bloody Legislation against the Expropriated, from the
end of the 15th. century: Forcing Down Wages by Acts of Parliament’ in Capital, 1986 686.
[11] Collins, H., Marxism and Law,
Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1987 24.
[12] O’Malley, P., ‘Theories on Structure Versus Causal Determination’
in Tomasic (ed.) Legislation and Society
in Australia,
Allen and Unwin, 1980 140.
[13] Marcuse, H., One-Dimensional
Man, Boston:
Beacon Press, 1968 xv.
[14] Marx. K., Preface To ‘A Contribution to the Critique of Political
Economy’ in Karl Marx and Friedrich
Engels Selected Works, 1989 521.
[15] Collins, H., op cit., 9.
[16] Gramsci, A., Selections from
the Prison Notebooks, London:
Lawrence and Wishart. 1971 195.
[17] Althusser, L., For Marx, London: New Left Books, 1977 114.
[18] Collins, H., Marxism and Law,
Oxford University Press, 1982 50.
[19] Marx, K., The German Ideology,
Moscow:
Progress Publishers, 1976 38.
[20] Giddens, A., Capitalism and
Modern Social Theory: An Analysis of the writings of Marx, Durkheim and Weber,
Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1971 21.
[22] Engels, F., Socialism:
Utopian and Scientific, Moscow:
Progress Publishers: 1954 79.
[23] Ibid., 73.
[24] Ibid., 73.
[25] Marx, K., The German Ideology,
Moscow Progress
Press, 1976 51.
[26] Wacks, R., Jurisprudence,
London:
Blackstone Press, 1987 175.
[27] Lukes, S., Marxism, Morality and Justice’ in Parkinson, G., Marx and Marxisms, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1982 197.
[28] Gamble, A., An Introduction
to Modern Political and Social Thought, Hampshire: Macmillan, 1987 101.
[29] Campbell, T., Justice, London: Macmillan, 1988
189.
[30] Campbell, T., The Left and
Rights, London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1983 33.
[31] Warrington,
R., ‘Pashukanis and the commodity form theory’ in Sugarman, D., Legality, Ideology and the State, London: Academic Press,
1983 43.
[32] Campbell, T. 1983, op cit., 123.
[33] Ibid., 124.
[35][2] See Rowan, 1999, p. 23-24; Sumner, 1987, p. 29.
Rowan writes: ¡°¡second order relations describe the ways in which the
first-order relations may be facilitated. In other words, they provide the
rules for manipulating the first-order relations.¡± This must be an imprecise
or loose explanation of conceptions other than first-order ones. Powers and
immunities can also stipulate and extinguish legal relations with the contents
of other powers and immunities. It would be more precise for the analysis of
Hohfeldian scheme to characterize these two conceptions as higher-order
conceptions.
[38][5] Rowan says,
¡°privileges also differs from claims in that they are not relational in
nature¡±, because a privilege is not correlative to a duty. (1999, p. 23) This
is obviously wrong, for a no-right indicates the same relation as the liberty
does.
[41][8] Sumner proposes that a liberty to do something
with respect to everyone is non-relational, for the reason that in this case
¡°I have no duty to anyone not to do it.¡± (1987, P. 26.) But if someone else
imposes his claim on me that I shall not do it, then he certainly violates my
liberty to do that. Equivalently, I do not have a duty to him not to do that.
Thus it is clear that I do have a liberty/no-claim relation to everyone.
[53] Marx, K., ‘Preface to A Contribution to the
Critique of Political Economy’ in Karl
Marx and Frederick Engels Selected Works, Moscow: Progress Press, 1989 521.
[54] Balbus, I., ‘Commodity Form and
Legal Form’ in Reasons, C., The Sociology
of Law, Toronto:
Butterworths, 1978 83.
[56] Barry, N., An Introduction to
Modern Political Theory, London:
Macmillan, 1989 53.
[57] Cain, M., and Hunt, A., 1979, Marx
and Engels on Law, London:
Academic Press.
[58] Ollman, B.,1976, Alienation;
Marx’s Conception of Man in Capitalist Society, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
[61] Marx, K., The German Ideology,
Moscow:
Progress Publishers, 1976 42.
[62] Marx, K., ‘Bloody Legislation against the Expropriated, from the
end of the 15th. century: Forcing Down Wages by Acts of Parliament’ in Capital, 1986 686.
[63] Collins, H., Marxism and Law,
Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1987 24.
[64] O’Malley, P., ‘Theories on Structure Versus Causal Determination’ in
Tomasic (ed.) Legislation and Society in Australia,
Allen and Unwin, 1980 140.
[65] Marcuse, H., One-Dimensional
Man, Boston:
Beacon Press, 1968 xv.
[66] Marx. K., Preface To ‘A Contribution to the Critique of Political
Economy’ in Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels
Selected Works, 1989 521.
[67] Collins, H., op cit., 9.
[68] Gramsci, A., Selections from
the Prison Notebooks, London:
Lawrence and Wishart. 1971 195.
[69] Althusser, L., For Marx, London: New Left Books, 1977 114.
[70] Collins, H., Marxism and Law,
Oxford University Press, 1982 50.
[71] Marx, K., The German Ideology,
Moscow:
Progress Publishers, 1976 38.
[72] Giddens, A., Capitalism and
Modern Social Theory: An Analysis of the writings of Marx, Durkheim and Weber,
Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1971 21.
[74] Engels, F., Socialism:
Utopian and Scientific, Moscow:
Progress Publishers: 1954 79.
[75] Ibid., 73.
[76] Ibid., 73.
[77] Marx, K., The German Ideology,
Moscow Progress
Press, 1976 51.
[78] Wacks, R., Jurisprudence,
London:
Blackstone Press, 1987 175.
[79] Lukes, S., Marxism, Morality and Justice’ in Parkinson, G., Marx and Marxisms, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1982 197.
[80] Gamble, A., An Introduction
to Modern Political and Social Thought, Hampshire: Macmillan, 1987 101.
[81] Campbell, T., Justice, London: Macmillan, 1988
189.
[82] Campbell, T., The Left and
Rights, London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1983 33.
[83] Warrington,
R., ‘Pashukanis and the commodity form theory’ in Sugarman, D., Legality, Ideology and the State, London: Academic Press,
1983 43.
[84] Campbell, T. 1983, op cit., 123.
[85] Ibid., 124.
No comments:
Post a Comment