THE CONCEPT OF JUSTICE IN JURISPRUDENCE


                                                  
The concept of justice is based upon and is equated with moral rightness (ethics), rationality, law, natural law, fairness, righteousness, equality, goodness, and equity.
What constitutes justice vary from society to society, person to person, from time to time and from place to place. It has thus been subject to various philosophical, legal, and theological reflections and debate.
Forms and variations of the concept of justice
1)      Utilitarianism- is a form where punishment is forward-looking
2)       Retributive justice- administers proportionate response to crime proven by lawful evidence, so that punishment is justly imposed and considered as morally-correct and fully deserved
3)      The law of retaliation (lex talionis)- this theory states that reciprocity should be equal to the wrong suffered (for example a person who commits murder should pay with his own life)
4)       Distributive justice- This is directed at the appropriate allocation of things meaning equal distribution among the equals. a just law in this case would be one which treats like situations alike, and an unjust law would be one that allocates rights and duties unequally without a plausible ground
5)      Corrective justice – corrective justice seeks to reinstate equality when this is disturbed. This comes into play when a norm of distributive justice has been breached or infringed by a member of a community. In such a situation, it becomes necessary to make amends for a wrong or deprive a party of an unjustified gain. This type of justice is generally administered by the court or other organ invested with judicial or quasi-judicial power. Its major areas of application are contracts, torts, and crimes.
Ancient philosophers
Ancient Indians, Greeks and Romans view of justice includes the whole of morality. They viewed justice as an ideal standard derived from God or based on Dharma (Indians)
Justice signifies a cluster of ideals and principles for common good and welfare without the least hope or opportunity of injustice, inequality or discrimination.
It is the notion of justice which directs our attention to the fairness and reasonableness of the rules, principles, and standards that are the ingredients of the normative structure.
CONTEMPORARY PHILOSOPHERS
 Contemporary philosophers think of justice as an important part of morality.
 HLA HART
Hart discusses his concept of justice and morality by indicating the relativity of the concept of justice. He indicates that justice is far more complicated because of  the shifting standard of relevant resemblance between different cases incorporated in it ,it also varies with the type of subject to which it is applied, and the fact that may often be open to challenge even in relation to a single type of subject.
Hart defines law as the combination of rules, making morality or justice as a necessary component of law through the rule of recognition.
He asserts that in cases where existing laws are vague or indeterminate, judicial discretion may be necessary in order to interpret and spell out existing laws or to look outside the law for standards to guide in supplementing old legal rules or creating new ones according to the community’s ideal of morality or justice.
Hart analyzes the concept of justice into a general principle with changeable criteria. He considers that administrative justice, one aspect of justice, has an essential connection with law.
According to Hart, the general concept of justice is connected with fairness. Evaluations using justice and injustice could use fair and unfair instead[1][1][1].
 The concept of justice applies to two primary types of circumstances-one is the distribution of benefits or burden upon individuals, and second is where wrongdoers compensate to the victims for the injuries caused. Apart from these two situations, justice can also be applied in trials and punishments.
Hart argues that the theory of treating like cases alike is not very fundamentals for analyzing administrative justice. It may cover the basics of impartiality because if decisions are guided solely by the criteria in rules there may not be room for prejudice and bias
Hart adopts Aristotle’s analysis of justice. So, the general precept of justice is that ‘Treat like cases alike and different cases differently’. As recognized by Aristotle however, this precept has to be supplemented by an account of relevant criteria for deciding whether the cases are similar or different
 Unfortunately, Hart does not provide a general theory or set of principle for determining which characteristics are relevant[2][2][2].
To Aristotle, a rule of justice was ‘natural’ if it had the same validity the world over. However, he did not take the stance that all the rules of justice were of this character. In particular, those of distributive justice depended, in his opinion, on shifting criteria of human equality and inequality. For example, he points out that the standards of equality are not the same in democratic, oligarchic, and aristocratic societies.
 St Thomas Aquinas viewed natural law as a set of realistic barriers which the universal and ineradicable traits of human beings, including their rational impulse of sociability, impose upon the powers of lawmakers.
Hart concludes that the law must be held to embrace all rules which are valid by virtue of the constitutional or statutory tests established by the positive legal system, regardless of the intrinsic justice of these rules
HANS KELSEN
According to Kelsen, justice means legality; happiness guaranteed by social order. It is just for a general rule to be actually applied in all cases which according to its content, this rule should apply. An injustice would arise if a law is applied in one case and not in another similar case. It seems unjust without regard to the value of the general rule itself, the application of which is under consideration.
The pure theory of law insists upon a clear separation of the concept of law from that of justice and renounces any justification of positive law by any kind of super laws.
NATURAL LAW ON JUSTICE
Natural law theory has been influential in the evolution of the human thought on the conception of justice for more than 2,500 years since its inception.  Friedmann says, ‘the history of natural law is a tale of the search of mankind for absolute justice and its failure’.
Justice, according to Ulpian is the constant and perpetual will to render to everyone that to which he is entitled'.  Earlier, Cicero had described justice as the disposition of the human mind to render to everyone his due.  This emphasizes the subjective aspect of justice but certain kinds of mental attitudes are not sufficient to capture all possible aspects of justice.  Acquinas, sought to improve on this definition by describing justice as a habit whereby a man renders to each his due by a constant and perpetual will.  .  
Plato identified justice with a harmonious relation between the various parts of the social organization[3][3][3].  Aristotle made distinction between general and particular justice and classified particular justice as distributive as well as corrective justice.  In a general sense, justice is a social virtue, while in the particular sense it means some sort of equality. Distributive justice, according to him, aims at an equal distribution of the social good among persons equal before the law. Corrective justice, on the other hand, aims at redressing an equality which has been interfered with.  It is usually administered by a court or other organs invested with judicial or quasi-judicial powers.  Distributive justice, in the view of Aristotle, is principally the concern of the legislator.
 The Christian Church injected the element of Christianity into the concept of justice and defined it to mean justice as ordained by the divine law.  Aquinas combined Aristotelian reason with the position of the church doctors, and defined justice to mean justice according to divine reason.  However, justice fell also within the measures of reason.
Social contract theorists like Hobbes and Locke used the concept of justice in the limited sense of contractual justice with Hobbes emphasizing  the need of  keeping  social contract but kept silence on modes of redressing injustice perpetrated by a ruler, Locke held the view that injustice was redressible by revolution if need be[4][4][4]. 

Justice is seen as an opposite to injustice, but both are two different and distinct concepts.  As McCoubrey and White put; justice is an aspiration which may be more or less closely approached by given societies but is unlikely ever to be perfectly attained in any human endeavour.  By contrast injustice is not directly associated with aspiration, it is rather a definition of the point at which a social order fails to attain or maintain a minimum acceptable standard and at which its 'legitimacy' is fundamentally called into question either in general or in some particular respect.
According to Aristotle, the term unjust is held to apply both to the person who breaks the law and the person who takes more than his due, the unfair man. Therefore, a person who abides by the law and the person who is fair are just men.
JOHN RAWLS
John Rawls perspective is a modern attempt to defend principles of justice. His conception of justice demands[5][5][5];
The maximization of liberty, subject only to such constraints as are essential for the protection of liberty itself,
Equality for all, both in the basic liberties of social life and also in distribution of all other forms of social goods, subject only to the exception that inequalities may be permitted if they produce the greatest possible benefit for those least well off in a given scheme of inequality (the difference principle),
‘Fair and equal opportunity’ and the elimination of all inequalities of opportunity based on birth or wealth.
Rawl’s Four-Staged Sequence for the attainment of a just society.
a)      The enunciation of the principles of justice from the original position.
b)      A partial lifting of the veil of ignorance so far as the general circumstances of the society but not the individual circumstances of the actors, the devising of a constitutional system dealing with the powers of the government and the rights of citizens.
c)      Having established a constitutional legislation in accordance with the principles of justices as well as the constitutional procedures. The legislators are intended to act in the light of the general interest rather than to their personal advantage.
d)      Application of the laws and the rules by judges and administrators          amd their working in the actions of people generally.
Criticizing Rawls theory of distributive justice, Hart says that the ‘principle of common interests’ breaks down in some important cases and that Rawls underestimates the difficulty of balancing conflicting liberties
APPLICATION OF THE CONCEPTS OF JUSTICE IN KENYA
Article 1 recognises the sovereignty of the people which may be exercised either directly or through democratically elected representatives and delegated to the three arms of government both at the national level and the county level, which qualifies hart’s concept of distributive justice.
Article 160 of the constitution provides for the constitution provides for the independence of the judiciary giving the judicial officers discretion to dispensing justice as per hart’s concept of construing vague laws.
Article 10 provides for the principles of governance to include equality, social justice, democracy and the rule of law which is binding on all state organs, state officers, public officers and all persons who enact, interpret or applies the constitution, any law or implements public policy decisions hence justifying Aristotle’s perspective on justice.
Article 27 provides for the equality of every person before the law and equal protection and benefit of the law as per Aristotle’s view on distributive justice, which according to him, aims at an equal distribution of the social good among persons equal before the law.
Article 159 vests judicial authority on the judiciary exercised by courts and tribunals who have the task of ensuring that justice is done to all irrespective of status and justice shall not be delayed.

JURISPRUDENCE AND EQUITY
Equity is generally acknowledged to be impossible to define completely. Almost everyone who has attempted to compose a definition of this word has ended by capitulating to the general view that the term has too many shades of meaning to be described definitively in one, or even several sentences. Equity can be defined as justice and impartiality. It can also be defined as the administration of law according to its spirit and not merely according to its letter. Equity ties the law with fairness. It is quality of being equal or fair; fairness in dealing.

Equity is that portion of the law which was developed by the English and American courts of Chancery to remedy defects in the common law. Second, and more important, it is that portion of the law which has been, or may be, enunciated for the purpose of meliorating any harsh or otherwise undesirable effects resulting from the strict application of any particular rule of law.

The growth of Equity as a part of English law was anticipated by a similar development of the same notions in Roman Jurisprudence. There has been a close relationship between the Roman jurisprudence and early English Common law. Equity is court developed law through Judgements and opinions given by judges. English courts have legislatively developed this branch of law and they continue to develop it.
The rules of Roman jurisprudence were based on morality and rules of nature and thus they were deemed impartial and fair. The principles guiding Roman jurisprudence based on natural law were introduced to the Roman jurisprudence hence constituting equity. Following the introduction of Christianity and after its influence had been felt throughout the then known world the meaning of aequitas became enlarged and was then made to include our modern of right, justice and morality.
Equity jurisprudence in the UK developed as a result of the petitions that were been made to the king who would listen to them and give his verdict. The petitions increased necessitating the creation of the courts of Chancery to hear the petition on behalf of the King. These petitions arose mainly as a result of the harshness of the common law and its inflexibility. It is through these courts that the principles of Equity as applicable today came about.
                                             
As the definition of equity suggests, equitable justice is a jurisprudence of discretionary judgment and exceptional situations. Historically, equity originated in the exercise of executive power by the English Chancellor, an officer of the king. The common law courts which developed in English jurisprudence by the end of the thirteenth century were The King's Bench, the Court of Common Pleas, and The Exchequer. Although each of these courts had jurisdiction over different subject matters, they were all regarded as "common law" courts, that is, courts governed by strict rules of law, a formalized procedure and bound by judicial precedent. At that point in time, the common law courts had no equity jurisprudence, and the Court of Chancery did not yet exist.
Beginning in the fourteenth century, the Chancellor, who was the King's Secretary, was responsible for issuing legal writs to complainants who wished to bring a legal action in one of the common law courts. Gradually, the Chancellor began to take it upon himself to resolve disputes for which no legal writ in a common law court was available. This was done under the theory that the Chancellor (as the King's agent) reserved the right to adjudicate cases which had not been expressly designated for one of the common law courts. Thus, the development of special writs for handling cases in the Chancellor's office (the Court of Chancery) became known as the "extraordinary" jurisdiction of the Chancellor.
The amount of cases handled by the Chancellor virtually exploded as more and more people sought these new writs as an alternative to seeking redress in the common law courts.
Equity is a jurisprudence of discretion. The basis of equity is the administration of grace, or discretion, to do justice. For equitable purposes, though, "justice" does not mean carrying out the law in any strict sense, but to do what the judge thinks is fair, regardless of the law. Consequently, equity is largely a matter of personal moral conscience freed from the restraints of law.
Equity spells out that law should be just. Justice in civil judgment requires that judges not apply the law in a partial way. That is, justice imposes a duty on every judge not to be a "respecter of persons. Naturalists believe that law is divine meaning it comes from God. God is not a respecter of persons, which means that His law applies uniformly to all people. This is also the standard for human laws. Accordingly, uniformity in the application of legal rules is a necessary element of justice. A law that is not uniform is not just.
APPLICATION OF EQUITY IN THE KENYAN LEGAL SYSTEM
     Section 3(1) (c) of the judicature Act of Kenya states as follows: The Jurisdiction of the High Court, Court of Appeal and the subordinate courts shall be exercised in conformity with: 
     subject thereto and so far as those written laws do not extend or apply, the substance of the common law, the doctrines of equity and the statutes of general applica­tion in force in England on the 12th August, 1897, and the procedure and practice observed in courts of justice in England at that date; but the common law, doctrines of equity and statutes of general application shall apply so far only as the circumstances of Kenya and its inhabitants permit and subject to such qualifications as those circumstances may render necessary.

Article 2(5) of the constitution of Kenya 2010 provides for the application of general principles of international law as part of the laws of Kenya. Doctrines of equity are widely practiced in many jurisdictions and thus can qualify as general principles of international law.
Article 10(2) (b) of the constitution of Kenya also provide for the application of Equity among other principles and values of national governance. These national principles and values shall bind all persons and state organs. Article 20(4) (a) provides that the courts shall apply equity in interpreting the bill of rights which all persons are entitled to enjoy to the fullest.
Article 47 of the constitution of Kenya 2010 provides that every person has a right to fair administrative action. Article 48 provides that every person has unlimited right to fair trial. These two provisions are in the spirit of fairness which is a constituting characteristic of equity. Article 159(2) (d) provides that courts shall strive to deliver justice without undue regard to procedural technicalities. One of the harshness of common law which equity came to cure was the rigidity of the law and its procedures. It follows then that article 159(2) (d) is in the spirit of doctrines of equity.
JURISPRUDENCE AND MORALITY
INTRODUCTION
The place and function of morals in the law has always been a focal concern of legal and political philosophers. As a result most of today's jurisprudence is centred on the question of morality and the law. The schools of thoughts in jurisprudence which bring out the full extent of the disagreements are legal positivists who seek to maintain a conceptual difference between law and morality and natural lawyers who reject the idea of a separation between law and morality as examined below:
Natural law school of thought
Most scholars in this school of thought have asserted that legal obligation is more in the nature of a command depending not on reason but on authority. In this respect, law resembles religion more closely than ethics for religion also appeals to authority in the sense of what is decreed by God.
Most natural law thinkers have reduced morals to a series of imperatives comparable to rules of law but these have often involved a close interconnection between religion and moral obligation.
Natural law thinking has therefore afforded a moral justification for existing social and economic systems and their legal systems. They have argued that what is the law is based on a higher law dictated by reason from an authority and so it is also what the law ought to be, positive law acquires a sanctity that puts it beyond question.
Natural law thinking at its core tries to provide a distinction between what is law and what ought to be law. Its principal claim is that what naturally is, ought to be. Some natural law thinkers and their views on morality are discussed below:


PLATO
The basis of ethics and other knowledge is in absolute values to which things could appropriate. Among the absolute values he identified include justice. From Plato's teachings, justice is an absolute value at which law should aim and law which can be bought with wealth is not thereby just.
For Plato ideas like justice, virtue and beauty were ideals but had greater ethical value than even the customs of particular regions. He located ethics in universal values which transcend the particularity of local practices and thus offered the prospect of a common ethics among different communities.
ARISTOTLE
He sought to identify values through the use of reason but unlike Plato he found that the values are glimpsed outside of this world (metaphysical) and not within the world.
Sources of values lie in nature that is human nature which has elements of change as well as stability.
He posited that man is a social being who needs social groups in order to flourish but that he was also a political animal who could participate in politics. Politics however is only possible within a city state or polis where one can find political debate. Thus for Aristotle, creation of polis allowed man to fulfil a potential which remained unfilled whilst he lived in small family groups.
He concluded that polis was not a threat to the small community but essential for the fulfilment of man's purpose. This reasoning led him to conclusions about the law appropriate to a polis for example man being a social animal must have laws appropriate for the rearing and education of the young. Aristotle regards natural justice as a species of political justice.
THOMAS AQUINAS
 He deployed Aristotle's philosophy in an effort to reconcile secular and Christian authority at a time when the Pope's authority was being undermined by want of a theological stance in respect of the exercise of secular power.
For Aquinas natural law is merely one element of divine providence: a participation in the eternal law which orders all creation. Its contents comprise principles of practical rationality by which human action is to be judged as reasonable or unreasonable.
According to him we are guided towards tenets of natural law by nature, they point us towards good as well as certain specific goods. At the heart of his interpretation of natural law is the basic notion that good is done and evil avoided and therefore we ought to pursue some specific good.
According to Aquinas, laws which conflict with the requirements of natural law lose their power to bind morally. Therefore a government which abuses its authority by enacting laws which are against the common good forfeits its right to be obeyed as it lacks moral authority.
JOHN FINNIS
He asserts that anyone who tries to explain law makes assumptions willingly about what is good.
In his book, Natural Law and Natural Rights, Finnis points out that the development of modern jurisprudence suggests that a theorist cannot give a theoretical description and analysis of social facts, unless he also participates in the work of evaluation, of understanding what is really good for human persons and what is really required by practical reasonableness.
LEGAL POSITIVISTS THEORIES
Legal positivists endeavour to combine the view that we can know things only through observation and rationalism. The fundamental principle in this school is the antagonism towards metaphysics. Legal positivism is concerned with the law as is and therefore attempts to identify the key features of the legal system that are posited by legislators, judges etc. Legal positivists therefore argue that there should be a distinction between law and morality.
A valuable starting point is discussing positivism is the summary of five main views associated with legal positivism provided by Professor H. L. A Hart in his essay 'Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals'
1)      That laws are commands of human beings
2)      That there is no necessary connection between law and morals
3)      That the analysis of legal concepts is worth pursuing distinct from sociological and historical enquiries and critical evaluation
4)      That a legal system is a closed logical system in which correct decisions may be deduced from predetermined legal rules by logical means alone
5)      Those moral judgments cannot be established as statements of facts can by rational argument, evidence, or proof.
Positivists share the view that the most effective method of analysing and understanding law and the legal system involves suspending moral judgment until it is established what it is we are seeking to explain.
SOCIOLOGICAL SCHOOL OF THOUGHT
Being cognizant of the definition of morality as the distinction between good or bad, one can determine or conclude that the sociological school of thought denies that morality and the law go hand in hand.
The sociological school of jurisprudence studies law in its socio-historic context. It is based on what society needs and desires in contemporary social conditions and concerned with the actual sources, effects and functions of law upon attitudes, behaviors, organization and powers involved in the maintenance of a particular society.
This school is therefore concerned with the law as is in a given society at a given time.
The origin of law according to the thinkers in this school lies in sociological factors, human conduct and social conditions obtaining in society.
VON JHERING
He states that the origin and ultimate purpose of the law is social control and therefore law is an instrument for serving society.
He asserts that although law has a coercive character it also has the binding character of social conventions and customs.
Law therefore has a social background and each society must find a law which best suits its purposes and aims. Law which is divorced from social realities and conditions is inadequate and incomplete therefore refute the idea that there is such a thing as eternal law.
ROSCOE POUND
He asserts that law must serve a particular function in society and the ultimate purpose of the law is social control. Law is not merely a set of law or legal order but it is a process of balancing conflicting social interests.
He posits that law's function is to adapt to the needs of a particular generation or period since the law is not based on any absolute ideals but on the views and attitudes of a particular society at a given period and time.
MORAL LAW IN THE CONSTITUTION OF KENYA 2010
Under the preamble of Kenya’s Constitution, the people of Kenya acknowledge the supremacy of the almighty God who is the creator of all things. The constitution therefore recognises the existence of a higher law than human made law. This is the eternal law of God. It therefore recognises the existence of higher moral principles which have validity and authority independent of human made law.
Article 10 of the Constitution lists the national values and principles of governance to include inter alia, human dignity, equity, social justice, equality, human rights, non discrimination and protection of the marginalised. These values and principles of governance have a moral force in the constitution and can be termed as moral law
The Bill of Rights under chapter four of the constitution is the fountain of moral law in Kenya’s legal system. It recognises and seeks to protect human rights and fundamental freedoms of individuals, groups and communities. For instance, the bill of rights recognises the right to life under article 26, freedom from slavery, servitude and forced labour.










[1][1][1] Ibid pp 154-155
[2][2][2] Ibid.
[3][3][3] Plato, The Republic, trans. A.D. Lindsey (1950)
[4][4][4] C.G. Weeramantry. An Invitation to Law (1988 Ind. ed.) p. 121
[5][5][5] A theory of justice first published in 1972

No comments:

Post a Comment